Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


Jump to content
WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
Search

Verificationism

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Philosophical doctrine

Verificationism, also known as theverification principle or theverifiability criterion of meaning, is adoctrine inphilosophy which asserts that a statement ismeaningful only if it is eitherempirically verifiable (can be confirmed through thesenses) or atautology (true by virtue of its ownmeaning or its ownlogical form). Verificationism rejects statements ofmetaphysics,theology,ethics andaesthetics as meaningless in conveyingtruth value orfactual content, though they may be meaningful in influencingemotions or behavior.[1]

Verificationism was a central thesis oflogical positivism, a movement inanalytic philosophy that emerged in the 1920s by philosophers who sought to unify philosophy and science under a commonnaturalistic theory of knowledge.[2] The verifiability criterion underwent various revisions throughout the 1920s to 1950s. However, by the 1960s, it was deemed to be irreparably untenable.[3] Its abandonment would eventually precipitate the collapse of the broader logical positivist movement.[4]

Origins

[edit]

The roots of verificationism may be traced to at least the 19th century, in philosophical principles that aim to ground scientific theory in verifiableexperience, such asC.S. Peirce'spragmatism and the work ofconventionalistPierre Duhem,[3] who fosteredinstrumentalism.[5]Verificationism, as principle, would be conceived in the 1920s by thelogical positivists of theVienna Circle, who sought anepistemology whereby philosophical discourse would be, in their perception, as authoritative and meaningful asempirical science.[6] The movement established grounding in theempiricism ofDavid Hume,[7]Auguste Comte andErnst Mach, and thepositivism of the latter two, borrowing perspectives fromImmanuel Kant and defining their exemplar of science inEinstein'sgeneral theory of relativity.[8]

Ludwig Wittgenstein'sTractatus, published in 1921, established the theoretical foundations for the verifiability criterion of meaning.[9] Building uponGottlob Frege's work, theanalytic–synthetic distinction was also reformulated, reducing logic and mathematics tosemantical conventions. This would render logical truths (beingunverifiable by the senses) tenable under verificationism, astautologies.[10]

Revisions

[edit]

Logical positivists within theVienna Circle recognized quickly that the verifiability criterion was too stringent. Specifically,universal generalizations were noted to be empirically unverifiable, rendering vital domains of science andreason, including scientifichypothesis,meaningless under verificationism, absent revisions to its criterion of meaning.[11]

Rudolf Carnap,Otto Neurath,Hans Hahn andPhilipp Frank led a faction seeking to make the verifiability criterion more inclusive, beginning a movement they referred to as the "liberalization of empiricism".Moritz Schlick andFriedrich Waismann led a "conservative wing" that maintained a strict verificationism. Whereas Schlick sought to redefine universal generalizations astautological rules, thereby to reconcile them with the existing criterion, Hahn argued that the criterion itself should be weakened to accommodate non-conclusive verification.[12] Neurath, within the liberal wing, proposed the adoption ofcoherentism, though challenged by Schlick'sfoundationalism. However, hisphysicalism would eventually be adopted overMach'sphenomenalism by most members of the Vienna Circle.[11][13]

With the publication of theLogical Syntax of Language in 1934, Carnap defined ‘analytic’ in a new way to account forGödel'sincompleteness theorem, who ultimately "thought that Carnap’s approach to mathematics could be refuted."[14] This method allowed Carnap to distinguish between a derivative relation between premises that can be obtained in a finite number of steps and a semantic consequence relation that has on all valuations the same truth value for the premise as the consequent. It follows that all sentences of pure mathematics individually, or their negation, are "a consequence of the null set of premises. This leaves Gödel’s results completely intact as they concerned what is provable, that is, derivable from the null set of premises or from any one consistent axiomatization of mathematical truths."[14]

In 1936, Carnap sought a switch from verification toconfirmation.[11] Carnap's confirmability criterion (confirmationism) would not require conclusive verification (thus accommodating for universal generalizations) but allow for partial testability to establishdegrees of confirmation on a probabilistic basis. Carnap never succeeded in finalising his thesis despite employing abundant logical and mathematical tools for this purpose. In all of Carnap's formulations, a universal law's degree of confirmation was zero.[15]

InLanguage, Truth and Logic, published that year,A. J. Ayer distinguished betweenstrong andweak verification. This system espoused conclusive verification, yet allowed for probabilistic inclusion where verifiability is inconclusive. He also distinguished theoretical from practical verifiability, proposing that statements that are verifiablein principle should be meaningful, even if unverifiable in practice.[16][17]

Criticisms

[edit]

PhilosopherKarl Popper, a graduate of theUniversity of Vienna, though not a member within the ranks of theVienna Circle, was among the foremost critics of verificationism. He identified three fundamental deficiencies in verifiability as a criterion of meaning:[18]

  • Verificationism rejectsuniversal generalizations, such as "all swans are white," as meaningless. Popper argues that while universal statements cannot be verified, they can be proven false, a foundation on which he was to propose his criterion offalsifiability.
  • Verificationism allows existential statements, such as “unicorns exist”, to be classified as scientifically meaningful, despite the absence of any definitive method to show that they are false (one could possibly find a unicorn somewhere not yet examined).
  • Verificationism is meaningless by virtue of its own criterion because it cannot be empirically verified. Thus the concept isself-defeating.

Popper regarded scientific hypotheses to never be completely verifiable, as well as notconfirmable underCarnap's thesis.[9][19] He also consideredmetaphysical,ethical andaesthetic statements often rich in meaning and important in the origination of scientific theories.[9]

Other philosophers also voiced their own criticisms of verificationism:

Falsifiability

[edit]
Main article:Falsifiability

InThe Logic of Scientific Discovery (1959), Popper proposedfalsifiability, orfalsificationism. Though formulated in the context of what he perceived were intractable problems in both verifiability and confirmability, Popper intended falsifiability, not as a criterion of meaning like verificationism (as commonly misunderstood),[25] but as a criterion todemarcate scientific statements from non-scientific statements.[9]

Notably, the falsifiability criterion would allow for scientific hypotheses (expressed asuniversal generalizations) to be held as provisionally true until proven false by observation, whereas under verificationism, they would be disqualified immediately as meaningless.[9]

In formulating his criterion, Popper was informed by the contrasting methodologies ofAlbert Einstein andSigmund Freud. Appealing to thegeneral theory of relativity and its predicted effects ongravitational lensing, it was evident to Popper that Einstein's theories carried significantly greaterpredictive risk than Freud's of being falsified byobservation. Though Freud found ample confirmation of his theories in observations, Popper would note that this method of justification was vulnerable toconfirmation bias, leading in some cases to contradictory outcomes. He would therefore conclude that predictive risk, orfalsifiability, should serve as the criterion to demarcate the boundaries of science.[26]

Though falsificationism has been criticized extensively by philosophers for methodological shortcomings in its intended demarcation of science,[18] it would receive acclamatory adoption among scientists.[19] Logical positivists too adopted the criterion, even as their movement ran its course, catapulting Popper, initially a contentious misfit, to carry the richest philosophy out of interwar Vienna.[25]

Legacy

[edit]

In 1967,John Passmore, a leading historian of 20th-century philosophy, wrote, "Logical positivism is dead, or as dead as a philosophical movement ever becomes".[4] Logical positivism's fall heraldedpostpositivism, where Popper's view of human knowledge as hypothetical, continually growing and open to change ascended[25] and verificationism, in academic circles, became mostly maligned.[3]

In a 1976 TV interview, A. J. Ayer, who had introduced logical positivism to theEnglish-speaking world in the 1930s[27] was asked what he saw as its main defects, and answered that "nearly all of it was false".[4] However, he soon said that he still held "the same general approach", referring to empiricism andreductionism, wherebymental phenomena resolve to the material or physical and philosophical questions largely resolve to ones of language and meaning.[4] In 1977, Ayer had noted:[3]

"The verification principle is seldom mentioned and when it is mentioned it is usually scorned; it continues, however, to be put to work. The attitude of many philosophers reminds me of the relationship between Pip and Magwitch inDickens'sGreat Expectations. They have lived on the money, but are ashamed to acknowledge its source."

In the late 20th and early 21st centuries, the general concept of verification criteria—in forms that differed from those of the logical positivists—was defended byBas van Fraassen,Michael Dummett,Crispin Wright,Christopher Peacocke,David Wiggins,Richard Rorty, and others.[3]

See also

[edit]

References

[edit]
  1. ^"Verifiability principle".Encyclopædia Britannica. 2024. Retrieved8 October 2024.
  2. ^Uebel, Thomas (2024)."Vienna Circle".Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved8 October 2024.
  3. ^abcdeMisak, C.J. (1995). "The Logical Positivists and the Verifiability Principle".Verificationism: Its History and Prospects. New York: Routledge.
  4. ^abcdHanfling, Oswald (1996). "Logical positivism". In Stuart G Shanker (ed.).Philosophy of Science, Logic and Mathematics in the Twentieth Century. Routledge. pp. 193–94.
  5. ^Epstein, Miran (2012). "Introduction to philosophy of science". In Clive Seale (ed.).Researching Society and Culture 3rd Ed. London: Sage Publications. pp. 18–19.
  6. ^Uebel 2024 Section 2.2
  7. ^Flew, Antony G (1984). "Science: Conjectures and refutations". In Andrew Bailey (ed.).A Dictionary of Philosophy. New York: St Martin's Press. p. 156. Despite Hume's radical empiricism, set forth near 1740, Hume was also committed tocommon sense and apparently did not take his own skepticism, such as theproblem of induction, as drastically as others later did.
  8. ^Uebel 2024 Section 3
  9. ^abcdePopper, Karl (2011). "Science: Conjectures and refutations". In Andrew Bailey (ed.).First Philosophy: Fundamental Problems and Readings in Philosophy (2 ed.). Peterborough Ontario: Broadview Press. pp. 338–42.
  10. ^Jerrold J. Katz (2000)."The epistemic challenge to antirealism".Realistic Rationalism. MIT Press. p. 69.ISBN 978-0262263290.
  11. ^abcSahotra Sarkar; Jessica Pfeifer, eds. (2006). "Rudolf Carnap".The Philosophy of Science: An Encyclopedia, Volume 1: A-M. New York: Routledge. p. 83.
  12. ^Uebel 2024 Section 3.1
  13. ^Flew 1984 p.245
  14. ^abCreath, Richard."Logical Empiricism".Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved9 March 2025.
  15. ^Murzi, Mauro (2001)."Rudolf Carnap (1891–1970)".Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  16. ^Ayer, A. J. (1936).Language, Truth, and Logic(PDF). pp. 6–7.
  17. ^Ayer, A. J. (29 November 2007)."Ayer on the criterion of verifiability"(PDF). Retrieved9 July 2023.
  18. ^abShea, Brendan."Karl Popper: Philosophy of Science".Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. RetrievedMay 12, 2019.
  19. ^abGodfrey-Smith, Peter (2005).Theory and Reality: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. pp. 57–59.
  20. ^Rocknak, Stefanie."Willard Van Orman Quine: The Analytic/Synthetic Distinction".Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. RetrievedJuly 14, 2024.
  21. ^Fetzer, James (2013)."Carl Hempel".Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved8 October 2024.
  22. ^Caldwell, Bruce (1994).Beyond Positivism: Economic Methodology in the 20th Century. London: Routledge. pp. 47–48.
  23. ^Okasha, Samir (2002). "Scientific Change and Scientific Revolutions".Philosophy of Science: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  24. ^Uebel 2024 Section 3.3
  25. ^abcHacohen, Malachi Haim (2000).Karl Popper: The Formative Years, 1902–1945: Politics and Philosophy in Interwar Vienna. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 212–13.
  26. ^Popper, Karl (1962).Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge (2 ed.). Routledge. pp. 34–37.
  27. ^Chapman, Siobhan (2009). "Logical positivism". In Siobhan Chapman; Christopher Routledge (eds.).Key ideas in linguistics and the philosophy of language. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
Related articles
Areas of focus
Turns
Logic
Theories
Concepts
Modality
Philosophers
Australian realism
Cambridge
Oxford
Logical positivists
Berlin Circle
Vienna Circle
Harvard
Notre Dame
Pittsburgh School
Pragmatism
Princeton
Quietism
Reformed
Science
Stanford School
Lwow-Warsaw
Perspectives
Declinations
Principal concepts
Antitheses
Relatedparadigm shifts
in thehistory of science
Related topics
Positivist-related debate
Method
Contributions
Proponents
Criticism
Critics
Concepts in contention
Authority control databases: NationalEdit this at Wikidata
Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Verificationism&oldid=1286845240"
Categories:
Hidden categories:

[8]ページ先頭

©2009-2025 Movatter.jp