Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


Jump to content
WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
Search

Transfinite induction

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Mathematical concept
Representation of the ordinal numbers up toωω{\displaystyle \omega ^{\omega }}. Each turn of the spiral represents one power ofω{\displaystyle \omega }. Transfinite induction requires proving abase case (used for 0), asuccessor case (used for those ordinals which have a predecessor), and alimit case (used for ordinals which don't have a predecessor).

Transfinite induction is an extension ofmathematical induction towell-ordered sets, for example to sets ofordinal numbers orcardinal numbers. Its correctness is a theorem ofZFC.[1]

Induction by cases

[edit]

LetP(α){\displaystyle P(\alpha )} be aproperty defined for all ordinalsα{\displaystyle \alpha }. Suppose that wheneverP(β){\displaystyle P(\beta )} is true for allβ<α{\displaystyle \beta <\alpha }, thenP(α){\displaystyle P(\alpha )} is also true.[2] Then transfinite induction tells us thatP{\displaystyle P} is true for all ordinals.

Usually the proof is broken down into three cases:

All three cases are identical except for the type of ordinal considered. They do not formally need to be considered separately, but in practice the proofs are typically so different as to require separate presentations. Zero is sometimes considered alimit ordinal and then may sometimes be treated in proofs in the same case as limit ordinals.

Transfinite recursion

[edit]

Transfinite recursion is similar to transfinite induction; however, instead of proving that something holds for all ordinal numbers, we construct a sequence of objects, one for each ordinal.

As an example, abasis for a (possibly infinite-dimensional)vector space can be created by starting with the empty set and for each ordinalα > 0 choosing a vector that is not in thespan of the vectors{vββ<α}{\displaystyle \{v_{\beta }\mid \beta <\alpha \}}. This process stops when no vector can be chosen.

More formally, we can state the Transfinite Recursion Theorem as follows:

Transfinite Recursion Theorem (version 1). Given a class function[3]G:VV (whereV is theclass of all sets), there exists a uniquetransfinite sequenceF: Ord →V (where Ord is the class of all ordinals) such that

F(α)=G(Fα){\displaystyle F(\alpha )=G(F\upharpoonright \alpha )} for all ordinalsα, where{\displaystyle \upharpoonright } denotes the restriction ofF's domain to ordinals < α.

As in the case of induction, we may treat different types of ordinals separately: another formulation of transfinite recursion is the following:

Transfinite Recursion Theorem (version 2). Given a setg1, and class functionsG2,G3, there exists a unique functionF: Ord →V such that

Note that we require the domains ofG2,G3 to be broad enough to make the above properties meaningful. The uniqueness of the sequence satisfying these properties can be proved using transfinite induction.

More generally, one can define objects by transfinite recursion on anywell-founded relationR. (R need not even be a set; it can be aproper class, provided it is aset-like relation; i.e. for anyx, the collection of ally such thatyRx is a set.)

Relationship to the axiom of choice

[edit]

Proofs or constructions using induction and recursion often use theaxiom of choice to produce a well-ordered relation that can be treated by transfinite induction. However, if the relation in question is already well-ordered, one can often use transfinite induction without invoking the axiom of choice.[4] For example, many results aboutBorel sets are proved by transfinite induction on the ordinal rank of the set; these ranks are already well-ordered, so the axiom of choice is not needed to well-order them.

The following construction of theVitali set shows one way that the axiom of choice can be used in a proof by transfinite induction:

First,well-order thereal numbers (this is where the axiom of choice enters via thewell-ordering theorem), giving a sequencerαα<β{\displaystyle \langle r_{\alpha }\mid \alpha <\beta \rangle }, where β is an ordinal with thecardinality of the continuum. Letv0 equalr0. Then letv1 equalrα1, whereα1 is least such thatrα1 − v0 is not arational number. Continue; at each step use the least real from ther sequence that does not have a rational difference with any element thus far constructed in thev sequence. Continue until all the reals in ther sequence are exhausted. The finalv sequence will enumerate the Vitali set.

The above argument uses the axiom of choice in an essential way at the very beginning, in order to well-order the reals. After that step, the axiom of choice is not used again.

Other uses of the axiom of choice are more subtle. For example, a construction by transfinite recursion frequently will not specify aunique value forAα+1, given the sequence up toα, but will specify only acondition thatAα+1 must satisfy, and argue that there is at least one set satisfying this condition. If it is not possible to define a unique example of such a set at each stage, then it may be necessary to invoke (some form of) the axiom of choice to select one such at each step. For inductions and recursions ofcountable length, the weakeraxiom of dependent choice is sufficient. Because there are models ofZermelo–Fraenkel set theory of interest to set theorists that satisfy the axiom of dependent choice but not the full axiom of choice, the knowledge that a particular proof only requires dependent choice can be useful.

See also

[edit]

Notes

[edit]
  1. ^J. Schlöder,Ordinal Arithmetic. Accessed 2022-03-24.
  2. ^It is not necessary here to assume separately thatP(0){\displaystyle P(0)} is true. As there is noβ{\displaystyle \beta } less than 0, it isvacuously true that for allβ<0{\displaystyle \beta <0},P(β){\displaystyle P(\beta )} is true.
  3. ^A class function is a rule (specifically, a logical formula) assigning each element in the lefthand class to an element in the righthand class. It is not afunction because its domain and codomain are not sets.
  4. ^In fact, the domain of the relation does not even need to be a set. It can be a proper class, provided that the relationR is set-like: for anyx, the collection of ally such thaty R x must be a set.

References

[edit]

External links

[edit]
General
Theorems (list)
 and paradoxes
Logics
Traditional
Propositional
Predicate
Set theory
Types ofsets
Maps and cardinality
Set theories
Formal systems (list),
language and syntax
Example axiomatic
systems
 (list)
Proof theory
Model theory
Computability theory
Related
Overview
Venn diagram of set intersection
Axioms
Operations
  • Concepts
  • Methods
Set types
Theories
Set theorists
Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Transfinite_induction&oldid=1253105247"
Categories:
Hidden categories:

[8]ページ先頭

©2009-2025 Movatter.jp