Ineconomics, anordinal utility function is a function representing thepreferences of an agent on anordinal scale. Ordinalutility theory claims that it is only meaningful to ask which option is better than the other, but it is meaningless to askhow much better it is or how good it is. All of the theory ofconsumer decision-making under conditions ofcertainty can be, and typically is, expressed in terms of ordinal utility.
For example, suppose George tells us that "I prefer A to B and B to C". George's preferences can be represented by a functionu such that:
But critics ofcardinal utility claim the only meaningful message of this function is the order; the actual numbers are meaningless. Hence, George's preferences can also be represented by the following functionv:
The functionsu andv are ordinally equivalent – they represent George's preferences equally well.
Ordinal utility contrasts withcardinal utility theory: the latter assumes that the differences between preferences are also important. Inu the difference between A and B is much smaller than between B and C, while inv the opposite is true. Hence,u andv arenot cardinally equivalent.
The ordinal utility concept was first introduced byPareto in 1906.[1]
Suppose the set of all states of the world is and an agent has a preference relation on. It is common to mark the weak preference relation by, so that reads "the agent wants B at least as much as A".
The symbol is used as a shorthand to the indifference relation:, which reads "The agent is indifferent between B and A".
The symbol is used as a shorthand to the strong preference relation: if:
Instead of defining a numeric function, an agent's preference relation can be represented graphically by indifference curves. This is especially useful when there are two kinds of goods,x andy. Then, each indifference curve shows a set of points such that, if and are on the same curve, then.
An example indifference curve is shown below:
Each indifference curve is a set of points, each representing a combination of quantities of two goods or services, all of which combinations the consumer is equally satisfied with. The further a curve is from the origin, the greater is the level of utility.
The slope of the curve (the negative of themarginal rate of substitution of X for Y) at any point shows the rate at which the individual is willing to trade off good X against good Y maintaining the same level of utility. The curve is convex to the origin as shown assuming the consumer has a diminishing marginal rate of substitution. It can be shown that consumer analysis with indifference curves (an ordinal approach) gives the same results as that based oncardinal utility theory — i.e., consumers will consume at the point where the marginal rate of substitution between any two goods equals the ratio of the prices of those goods (the equi-marginal principle).
Revealed preference theory addresses the problem of how to observe ordinal preference relations in the real world. The challenge of revealed preference theory lies in part in determining what goods bundles were foregone, on the basis of them being less liked, when individuals are observed choosing particular bundles of goods.[2][3]
Some conditions on are necessary to guarantee the existence of a representing function:
When these conditions are met and the set is finite, it is easy to create a function which represents by just assigning an appropriate number to each element of, as exemplified in the opening paragraph. The same is true when X iscountably infinite. Moreover, it is possible to inductively construct a representing utility function whose values are in the range.[4]
When is infinite, these conditions are insufficient. For example,lexicographic preferences are transitive and complete, but they cannot be represented by any utility function.[4] The additional condition required iscontinuity.
A preference relation is calledcontinuous if, whenever B is preferred to A, small deviations from B or A will not reverse the ordering between them. Formally, a preference relation on a set X is called continuous if it satisfies one of the following equivalent conditions:
If a preference relation is represented by a continuous utility function, then it is clearly continuous. By the theorems ofDebreu (1954), the opposite is also true:
Note that thelexicographic preferences are not continuous. For example,, but in every ball around (5,1) there are points with and these points are inferior to. This is in accordance with the fact, stated above, that these preferences cannot be represented by a utility function.
For every utility functionv, there is a unique preference relation represented byv. However, the opposite is not true: a preference relation may be represented by many different utility functions. The same preferences could be expressed asany utility function that is a monotonically increasing transformation ofv. E.g., if
where isany monotonically increasing function, then the functionsv andv give rise to identical indifference curve mappings.
This equivalence is succinctly described in the following way:
In contrast, acardinal utility function is unique up to increasingaffine transformation. Every affine transformation is monotone; hence, if two functions are cardinally equivalent they are also ordinally equivalent, but not vice versa.
Suppose, from now on, that the set is the set of all non-negative real two-dimensional vectors. So an element of is a pair that represents the amounts consumed from two products, e.g., apples and bananas.
Then under certain circumstances a preference relation is represented by a utility function.
Suppose the preference relation ismonotonically increasing, which means that "more is always better":
Then, both partial derivatives, if they exist, ofv are positive. In short:
Suppose a person has a bundle and claims that he is indifferent between this bundle and the bundle. This means that he is willing to give units of x to get units of y. If this ratio is kept as, we say that is themarginal rate of substitution (MRS) betweenx andy at the point.[5]: 82
This definition of the MRS is based only on the ordinal preference relation – it does not depend on a numeric utility function. If the preference relation is represented by a utility function and the function is differentiable, then the MRS can be calculated from the derivatives of that function:
For example, if the preference relation is represented by then. The MRS is the same for the function. This is not a coincidence as these two functions represent the same preference relation – each one is an increasing monotone transformation of the other.
In general, the MRS may be different at different points. For example, it is possible that at the MRS is low because the person has a lot ofx and only oney, but at or the MRS is higher. Some special cases are described below.
When the MRS of a certain preference relation does not depend on the bundle, i.e., the MRS is the same for all, the indifference curves are linear and of the form:
and the preference relation can be represented by a linear function:
(Of course, the same relation can be represented by many other non-linear functions, such as or, but the linear function is simplest.)[5]: 85
When the MRS depends on but not on, the preference relation can be represented by aquasilinear utility function, of the form
where is a certain monotonically increasing function. Because the MRS is a function, a possible function can be calculated as an integral of:[6][5]: 87
In this case, all the indifference curves are parallel – they are horizontal transfers of each other.
A more general type of utility function is anadditive function:
There are several ways to check whether given preferences are representable by an additive utility function.
If the preferences are additive then a simple arithmetic calculation shows that
so this "double-cancellation" property is a necessary condition for additivity.
Debreu (1960) showed that this property is also sufficient: i.e., if a preference relation satisfies the double-cancellation property then it can be represented by an additive utility function.[7]
If the preferences are represented by an additive function, then a simple arithmetic calculation shows that
so this "corresponding tradeoffs" property is a necessary condition for additivity. This condition is also sufficient.[8][5]: 91
When there are three or more commodities, the condition for the additivity of the utility function is surprisinglysimpler than for two commodities. This is an outcome ofTheorem 3 of Debreu (1960). The condition required for additivity ispreferential independence.[5]: 104
A subset A of commodities is said to bepreferentially independent of a subset B of commodities, if the preference relation in subset A, given constant values for subset B, is independent of these constant values. For example, suppose there are three commodities:xy andz. The subset {x,y} is preferentially-independent of the subset {z}, if for all:
In this case, we can simply say that:
Preferential independence makes sense in case ofindependent goods. For example, the preferences between bundles of apples and bananas are probably independent of the number of shoes and socks that an agent has, and vice versa.
By Debreu's theorem, if all subsets of commodities are preferentially independent of their complements, then the preference relation can be represented by an additive value function. Here we provide an intuitive explanation of this result by showing how such an additive value function can be constructed.[5] The proof assumes three commodities:x,y,z. We show how to define three points for each of the three value functions: the 0 point, the 1 point and the 2 point. Other points can be calculated in a similar way, and then continuity can be used to conclude that the functions are well-defined in their entire range.
0 point: choose arbitrary and assign them as the zero of the value function, i.e.:
1 point: choose arbitrary such that. Set it as the unit of value, i.e.:
Choose and such that the following indifference relations hold:
This indifference serves to scale the units ofy andz to match those ofx. The value in these three points should be 1, so we assign
2 point: Now we use the preferential-independence assumption. The relation between and is independent ofz, and similarly the relation between and is independent ofx and the relation between and is independent ofy. Hence
This is useful because it means that the functionv can have the same value – 2 – in these three points. Select such that
and assign
3 point: To show that our assignments so far are consistent, we must show that all points that receive a total value of 3 are indifference points. Here, again, the preferential independence assumption is used, since the relation between and is independent ofz (and similarly for the other pairs); hence
and similarly for the other pairs. Hence, the 3 point is defined consistently.
We can continue like this by induction and define the per-commodity functions in all integer points, then use continuity to define it in all real points.
An implicit assumption in point 1 of the above proof is that all three commodities areessential orpreference relevant.[7]: 7 This means that there exists a bundle such that, if the amount of a certain commodity is increased, the new bundle is strictly better.
The proof for more than 3 commodities is similar. In fact, we do not have to check that all subsets of points are preferentially independent; it is sufficient to check a linear number of pairs of commodities. E.g., if there are different commodities,, then it is sufficient to check that for all, the two commodities are preferentially independent of the other commodities.[5]: 115
An additive preference relation can be represented by many different additive utility functions. However, all these functions are similar: they are not only increasing monotone transformations of each other (as are all utility functions representing the same relation); they are increasinglinear transformations of each other.[7]: 9 In short,
The mathematical foundations of most common types of utility functions — quadratic and additive — laid down byGérard Debreu[9][10]enabledAndranik Tangian to develop methods for their construction from purely ordinal data.In particular, additive and quadratic utility functions in variables can be constructed from interviews of decision makers, where questions are aimed at tracing totally 2D-indifference curves in coordinate planes without referring to cardinal utility estimates.[11][12]
The following table compares the two types of utility functions common in economics:
Level of measurement | Representspreferences on | Unique up to | Existence proved by | Mostly used in | |
---|---|---|---|---|---|
Ordinal utility | Ordinal scale | Sure outcomes | Increasingmonotone transformation | Debreu (1954) | Consumer theory under certainty |
Cardinal utility | Interval scale | Random outcomes (lotteries) | Increasing monotonelinear transformation | Von Neumann-Morgenstern (1947) | Game theory,choice under uncertainty |
{{cite book}}
:ISBN / Date incompatibility (help)