Part of a series on |
Philosophy |
---|
![]() |
Metaphilosophy, sometimes calledthe philosophy of philosophy, is "the investigation of the nature ofphilosophy".[1] Its subject matter includes the aims of philosophy, the boundaries of philosophy, and its methods.[2][3] Thus, while philosophy characteristically inquires into the nature ofbeing, the reality of objects, the possibility of knowledge, the nature oftruth, and so on, metaphilosophy is theself-reflective inquiry into the nature, aims, and methods of the activity that makes these kinds of inquiries, by asking whatis philosophy itself, what sorts of questions it should ask, how it might pose and answer them, and what it can achieve in doing so. It is considered by some to be a subject prior and preparatory to philosophy,[4] while others see it as inherently a part of philosophy,[5] or automatically a part of philosophy[6] while others adopt some combination of these views.[2]
The interest in metaphilosophy led to the establishment of the journalMetaphilosophy in January 1970.[7]
Many sub-disciplines of philosophy have their own branch of 'metaphilosophy', examples beingmeta-aesthetics,meta-epistemology,meta-ethics, andmetametaphysics (meta-ontology).[8]
Although theterm metaphilosophy and explicit attention to metaphilosophy as a specific domain within philosophy arose in the 20th century, the topic is likely as old as philosophy itself, and can be traced back at least as far as the works ofAncient Greeks and Ancient IndianNyaya.[9]
Some philosophers consider metaphilosophy to be a subject apart from philosophy, above or beyond it,[4] while others object to that idea.[5]Timothy Williamson argues that the philosophy of philosophy is "automatically part of philosophy", as is the philosophy of anything else.[6] Nicholas Bunnin andJiyuan Yu write that the separation of first- from second-order study has lost popularity as philosophers find it hard to observe the distinction.[10] As evidenced by these contrasting opinions, debate persists as to whether the evaluation of the nature of philosophy is 'second-order philosophy' or simply 'plain philosophy'.
Many philosophers have expressed doubts over the value of metaphilosophy.[11] Among them isGilbert Ryle: "preoccupation with questions about methods tends to distract us from prosecuting the methods themselves. We run as a rule, worse, not better, if we think a lot about our feet. So let us ... not speak of it all but just do it."[12]
The designationsmetaphilosophy andphilosophy of philosophy have a variety of meanings, sometimes taken to be synonyms, and sometimes seen as distinct.
Morris Lazerowitz claims to have coined the term 'metaphilosophy' around 1940 and used it in print in 1942.[1] Lazerowitz proposed that metaphilosophy is 'the investigation of the nature of philosophy'.[1] Earlier uses have been found in translations from French.[13] The term is derived fromGreek wordmeta μετά ("after", "beyond", "with") andphilosophía φιλοσοφία ("love of wisdom").
The term 'metaphilosophy' is used byPaul Moser[14] in the sense of a 'second-order' or more fundamental undertaking than philosophy itself, in the manner suggested byCharles Griswold:[4]
"The distinction between philosophy and metaphilosophy has an analogue in the familiar distinction between mathematics and metamathematics."[14]
— Paul K. Moser,Metaphilosophy,p. 562
Some other philosophers treat the prefixmeta as simply meaning 'about...', rather than as referring to ametatheoretical 'second-order' form of philosophy, among themRescher[15] and Double.[16] Others, such asWilliamson, prefer the term'philosophy of philosophy' instead of 'metaphilosophy' as it avoids the connotation of a 'second-order' discipline that looks down on philosophy, and instead denotes something that is a part of it.[17] Joll suggests that to take metaphilosophy as 'the application of the methods of philosophy to philosophy itself' is too vague, while the view that sees metaphilosophy as a 'second-order' or more abstract discipline, outside philosophy, "is narrow and tendentious".[18]
In theanalytic tradition, the term "metaphilosophy" is mostly used to tag commenting and research on previous works as opposed to original contributions towards solvingphilosophical problems.[19]
Ludwig Wittgenstein wrote about the nature of philosophical puzzles and philosophical understanding. He suggested philosophical errors arose from confusions about the nature of philosophical inquiry.
C. D. Broad distinguished Critical from Speculative philosophy in his "The Subject-matter of Philosophy, and its Relations to the special Sciences", inIntroduction to Scientific Thought, 1923.Curt Ducasse, inPhilosophy as a Science, examines several views of the nature of philosophy, and concludes that philosophy has a distinct subject matter:appraisals. Ducasse's view has been among the first to be described as 'metaphilosophy'.[20]
Henri Lefebvre inMétaphilosophie (1965) argued, from a Marxian standpoint, in favor of an "ontological break", as a necessary methodological approach for critical social theory (whilst criticizingLouis Althusser's "epistemological break" with subjective Marxism, which represented a fundamental theoretical tool for the school of Marxist structuralism).
Paul Moser writes that typical metaphilosophical discussion includes determining the conditions under which a claim can be said to be a philosophical one. He regardsmeta-ethics, the study ofethics, to be a form of metaphilosophy, as well asmeta-epistemology, the study ofepistemology.[14]
Many sub-disciplines of philosophy have their own branch of 'metaphilosophy'.[8] However, some topics within 'metaphilosophy' cut across the various subdivisions of philosophy to consider fundamentals important to all its sub-disciplines.
Some philosophers (e.g.existentialists,pragmatists) think philosophy is ultimately a practical discipline that should help us lead meaningful lives by showing us who we are, how we relate to the world around us and what we should do.[citation needed] Others (e.g.analytic philosophers) see philosophy as a technical, formal, and entirely theoretical discipline, with goals such as "the disinterested pursuit of knowledge for its own sake".[21] Other proposed goals of philosophy include discovering the absolutely fundamental reason of everything it investigates, making explicit the nature and significance of ordinary and scientific beliefs,[22] and unifying and transcending the insights given by science and religion.[23] Others proposed that philosophy is a complex discipline because it has 4 or 6 different dimensions.[24][25]
Defining philosophy and its boundaries is itself problematic;Nigel Warburton has called it "notoriously difficult".[26] There is no straightforward definition,[23] and most interesting definitions are controversial.[27] AsBertrand Russell wrote:
"We may note one peculiar feature of philosophy. If someone asks the question what is mathematics, we can give him a dictionary definition, let us say the science of number, for the sake of argument. As far as it goes this is an uncontroversial statement... Definitions may be given in this way of any field where a body of definite knowledge exists. But philosophy cannot be so defined. Any definition is controversial and already embodies a philosophic attitude. The only way to find out what philosophy is, is to do philosophy."[28]
— Bertrand Russell,The Wisdom of the West, p. 7
While there is some agreement that philosophy involves general or fundamental topics,[21][29] there is no clear agreement about a series of demarcation issues, including:
Philosophical method (or philosophical methodology) is the study of how to do philosophy. A common view among philosophers is that philosophy is distinguished by the ways that philosophers follow in addressing philosophical questions. There is not just one method that philosophers use to answer philosophical questions.
C.D. Broad classifies philosophy into two methods, he distinguished between critical philosophy and speculative philosophy. He described critical philosophy as analysing "unanalysed concepts in daily life and in science" and then "expos[ing] them to every objection that we can think of". While speculative philosophy's role is to "take over all aspects of human experience, to reflect upon them, and to try to think out a view of Reality as a whole which shall do justice to all of them".[34]
Recently, some philosophers have cast doubt about intuition as a basic tool in philosophical inquiry, from Socrates up to contemporary philosophy of language. InRethinking Intuition[35] various thinkers discard intuition as a valid source of knowledge and thereby call into question 'a priori' philosophy.Experimental philosophy is a form of philosophical inquiry that makes at least partial use ofempirical research—especiallyopinion polling—in order to address persistentphilosophical questions. This is in contrast with the methods found inanalytic philosophy, whereby some say a philosopher will sometimes begin by appealing to his or herintuitions on an issue and then form anargument with those intuitions aspremises. However, disagreement about what experimental philosophy can accomplish is widespread and several philosophers have offeredcriticisms. One claim is that the empirical data gathered by experimental philosophers can have an indirect effect on philosophical questions by allowing for a better understanding of the underlying psychological processes which lead to philosophical intuitions.[36] Some analytic philosophers like Timothy Williamson[37] have rejected such a move against 'armchair' philosophy–i.e., philosophical inquiry that is undergirded by intuition–by construing 'intuition' (which they believe to be a misnomer) as merely referring to common cognitive faculties: If one is calling into question 'intuition', one is, they would say, harboring a skeptical attitude towards common cognitive faculties–a consequence that seems philosophically unappealing. For Williamson, instances of intuition are instances of our cognitive faculties processing counterfactuals[38] (or subjunctive conditionals) that are specific to the thought experiment or example in question.
A prominent question in metaphilosophy is whether philosophical progress occurs and, moreover, whether such progress in philosophy is even possible.[39]
David Chalmers divides inquiry into philosophical progress in metaphilosophy into three questions.
Ludwig Wittgenstein, inCulture and Value remarked, "Philosophy hasn't made any progress? - If somebody scratches the spot where he has an itch, do we have to see some progress?...And can't this reaction to an irritation continue in the same way for a long time before the cure for an itching is discovered?".[41]
According toHilary Putnam philosophy is more adept at showing people that specific ideas or arguments are wrong than that specific ideas or arguments are right.[42]
Its primary question is "What is philosophy?"
{{cite book}}
:ISBN / Date incompatibility (help)The philosophy of philosophy is automatically part of philosophy, just as the philosophy of anything else is...
"Insofar as conceptual analysis is the method of philosophy (as it was widely held to be for much of the twentieth century), philosophy is a second-order subject because it is about language not the world or what language is about.
The important difference between the scientist and the philosopher is in the radically critical nature of philosophy.Husserl characterizes this difference by saying that the task of philosophy is to ask the ultimate questions...The philosophical questions can not be answered in the same way that empirical questions can be answered.
The sciences are in need of continual epistemological reflection and critique of a sort that only the philosopher can provide. ...Husserl pictures the work of the philosopher and the scientist as mutually complementary.