Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


Jump to content
WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
Search

Ideal speech situation

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
This article has multiple issues. Please helpimprove it or discuss these issues on thetalk page.(Learn how and when to remove these messages)
This articlemay beconfusing or unclear to readers. Please helpclarify the article. There might be a discussion about this onthe talk page.(October 2010) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
This article includes a list ofgeneral references, butit lacks sufficient correspondinginline citations. Please help toimprove this article byintroducing more precise citations.(March 2012) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
(Learn how and when to remove this message)

Anideal speech situation was a term introduced in the early philosophy ofJürgen Habermas. It argues that an ideal speech situation is found whencommunication between individuals is governed by basic, implied rules. In an ideal speech situation, participants would be able to evaluate each other’s assertions solely on the basis of reason and evidence in an atmosphere completely free of any nonrational “coercive” influences, including both physical and psychological coercion. Furthermore, all participants would be motivated solely by the desire to obtain a rational consensus.

Doctrines

[edit]

Members of the public sphere must adhere to certain rules for an "ideal speech situation" to occur. They are:

1. Every subject with the competence to speak and act is allowed to take part in a discourse.

2a. Everyone is allowed to question anyassertion whatever.

2b. Everyone is allowed to introduce any assertion whatever into the discourse.

2c. Everyone is allowed to express their attitudes, desires and needs without any hesitation.

3. No speaker may be prevented, by internal or external coercion, from exercising his rights as laid down in (1) and (2)[1]

The concept of the ideal speech situation came under attack in the 1970s by theorists who persistentlyrelativized the concept, arguing that anyparticular conception of an ideal speech situation could not be proven completely correct, so that any (still-unknown) gaps could allow associated oppressions to arise or persist.

Habermas responded to this in 1983 withMoral Consciousness and Communicative Action (English trans. 1990). In this work he no longer spoke of a known ideal speech situation but instead of a newmoral system ("Discourse ethics") that could be derived from the "presuppositions of argumentation". These, in turn, couldinitially be postulated by philosophical analysis in the same way thatImmanuel Kant tried to justify his own moral system throughtranscendental arguments. However, unlike Kant, Habermas recognizes that the presuppositions of argumentation can be tested in practice by a device he terms "performative contradiction". If critics object to the presuppositions of argumentation, their argumentmight be turned on them to demonstrate that their argument has already granted the existence of whatever specific presupposition of argument they object to. However, if such a performativecontradiction cannot be found, then the presuppositions of argumentation must be revised to take account of the criticism and the moral system derived from these presuppositions altered accordingly. In other words, "performative contradiction" is not a trump card to dismiss all objections but a fair test of those objections. Thedialectical nature of Habermas's argument often goes unrecognized.

Use in pragmatics and speech-act analysis

[edit]

The ideal speech situation, in its assumption of literal rather than figurative language function (language "below" rather than "above" the context-forming horizon of the lifeworld), is taken as the model for formalpragmatic analysis ofspeech-acts.

See also

[edit]

Notes

[edit]
  1. ^Habermas, Jurgen. "Discourse Ethics: Notes on a Program of Philosophical Justification." Moral Consciousnessand Communicative Action. Trans. Christian Lenhart and Shierry Weber Nicholson.Cambridge: MIT Press, 1990, pp. 43-115.

References

[edit]
  • 1973a. Wahrheitstheorien. In H. Fahrenbach (ed.), Wirklichkeit und Reflexion. Pfüllingen: Neske. 211–265. Reprint: 1984b, chap. 2.
  • 1971/2001. Reflections on the linguistic foundations of sociology: The Christian Gauss Lectures (Princeton University, February–March 1971). * In Habermas, On the Pragmatics of Social Interaction, B. Fultner (trans.). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2001. 1–103. [German, 1984b, chap. 1]

External links

[edit]
Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Ideal_speech_situation&oldid=1221265846"
Categories:
Hidden categories:

[8]ページ先頭

©2009-2025 Movatter.jp