Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


Jump to content
WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
Search

Function (biology)

This is a good article. Click here for more information.
From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Reason for a change under natural selection; in physiology, what a system does

Inevolutionary biology,function is the reason some object or process occurred in a system thatevolved throughnatural selection. That reason is typically that it achieves some result, such as thatchlorophyll helps to capture the energy of sunlight inphotosynthesis. Hence, the organism that contains it is more likely to survive and reproduce, in other words the function increases the organism'sfitness. A characteristic that assists in evolution is called anadaptation; other characteristics may be non-functionalspandrels, though these in turn may later be co-opted by evolution to serve new functions.

Inbiology, function has been defined in many ways. Inphysiology, it is simply what an organ, tissue, cell or molecule does.

In thephilosophy of biology, talk of function inevitably suggests some kind ofteleological purpose, even though natural selection operates without any goal for the future. All the same,biologists often use teleological language as a shorthand for function. In contemporary philosophy of biology, there are three major accounts of function in the biological world: theories of causal role, selected effect, and goal contribution.

In pre-evolutionary biology

[edit]
Further information:Four causes andAristotle's biology

Inphysiology, a function is an activity or process carried out by a system in anorganism, such assensation orlocomotion in an animal.[1] Thisconcept of function as opposed toform (respectively Aristotle'sergon andmorphê[2]) was central in biological explanations inclassical antiquity. In more modern times it formed part of the 1830Cuvier–Geoffroy debate, where Cuvier argued that an animal's structure was driven by its functional needs, while Geoffroy proposed that each animal's structure was modified from a common plan.[3][4][5]

In evolutionary biology

[edit]

Function can be defined in a variety of ways,[6][7] including as adaptation,[8] as contributing to evolutionary fitness,[9] in animal behaviour,[10] and, as discussed below, also as some kind of causal role or goal in the philosophy of biology.[11]

Adaptation

[edit]
Main article:Adaptation

A functional characteristic is known inevolutionary biology as anadaptation, and the research strategy for investigating whether a character is adaptive is known asadaptationism. Although assuming that acharacter is functional may be helpful in research, some characteristics of organisms are non-functional, formed as accidentalspandrels, side effects of neighbouring functional systems.[8]

Natural selection

[edit]
Chlorophyll molecule has a function inphotosynthesis.
Main article:Natural selection

From the point of view ofnatural selection, biological functions exist to contribute tofitness, increasing the chance that an organism will survive toreproduce.[9][12] For example, the function ofchlorophyll in a plant is to capture the energy of sunlight forphotosynthesis,[13] which contributes toevolutionary success.[14]

In ethology

[edit]
Main article:Tinbergen's four questions

TheethologistNiko Tinbergen named four questions, based onAristotle'sFour Causes,[10] that a biologist could ask to help explain abehaviour, though they have been generalised to a wider scope. 1) Mechanism: What mechanismscause the animal to behave as it does? 2)Ontogeny: Whatdevelopmental mechanisms in the animal's embryology (and its youth, if itlearns) created the structures that cause the behaviour? 3) Function/adaptation: What is the evolutionary function of the behaviour? 4) Evolution: What is thephylogeny of the behaviour, or in other words, when did it first appear in the evolutionary history of the animal? The questions are interdependent, so that, for example, adaptive function is constrained by embryonic development.[15][16][17][18]

In philosophy of biology

[edit]
Main article:Teleology in biology
"Behaviour with a purpose": a youngspringbokstotting.[11][19] A philosopher of biology might argue that this has the function ofsignalling to predators, helping the springbok to survive and allowing it to reproduce.[11]

Function is not the same as purpose in theteleological sense, that is, possessing conscious mental intention to achieve a goal. In thephilosophy of biology,evolution is a blind process which has no 'goal' for the future. For example, a tree does not grow flowers for any purpose, but does so simply because it has evolved to do so. To say 'a tree growsflowers to attractpollinators' would be incorrect if the 'to' implies purpose. A function describes what somethingdoes, not what its 'purpose' is. However,teleological language is often used by biologists as a shorthand way of describing function, even though its applicability is disputed.[11]

In contemporary philosophy of biology, there are three major accounts of function in the biological world: theories of causal role,[20] selected effect,[21] and goal contribution.[22]

Causal role

[edit]

Causal role theories of biological function trace their origin back to a 1975 paper by Robert Cummins.[20] Cummins defines the functional role of a component of a system to be the causal effect that the component has on the larger containing system. For example, the heart has the actual causal role of pumping blood in the circulatory system; therefore, the function of the heart is to pump blood. This account has been objected to on the grounds that it is too loose a notion of function. For example, the heart also has the causal effect of producing a sound, but we would not consider producing sound to be the function of the heart.[23][24]

Selected effect

[edit]
Further information:Natural selection

Selected effect theories of biological functions hold that the function of a biological trait is the function that the trait wasselected for, as argued by Ruth Millikan.[21] For example, the function of the heart is pumping blood, for that is the action for which the heart was selected for by evolution. In other words, pumping blood isthe reason that the heart has evolved. This account has been criticized for being too restrictive a notion of function. It is not always clear which behavior has contributed to the selection of a trait, as biological traits can have functions, even if they have not been selected for. Beneficialmutations are initially not selected for, but they do have functions.[25]

Goal contribution

[edit]

Goal contribution theories seek to carve a middle ground between causal role and selected effect theories, as with Boorse (1977).[22] Boorse defines the function of a biological trait to be the statistically typical causal contribution of that trait to survival and reproduction. So for example, zebra stripes were sometimes said to workby confusing predators. This role of zebra stripes would contribute to the survival and reproduction of zebras, and that is why confusing predators would be said to be the function of zebra stripes. Under this account, whether or not a particular causal role of a trait is its function depends on whether that causal role contributes to the survival and reproduction of that organism.[26]

See also

[edit]

References

[edit]
  1. ^Fletcher, John (1837).On the functions of organized beings, and their arrangement. John Carfrae & Son. pp. 1–15.{{cite book}}:|work= ignored (help)
  2. ^Tipton, Jason A. (2014).Philosophical Biology in Aristotle'sParts of Animals. Springer. p. 33.ISBN 978-3-319-01421-0. citingThe Parts of Animals 640–641.
  3. ^Russell, Edward Stewart (1916).Form and Function: A Contribution to the History of Animal Morphology. John Murray.Archived from the original on 2023-06-12. Retrieved2018-01-14.
  4. ^Asma, S. T. (1996).Following form and function: A philosophical archaeology of life science. Northwestern University Press.ISBN 9780810113978.
  5. ^Arber, Agnes (1950).The Natural Philosophy of Plant Form. Cambridge University Press.
  6. ^Toepfer, G. (2011). "Funktion".Historisches Wörterbuch der Biologie. Geschichte und Theorie der biologischen Grundbegriffe(PDF) (in German). Vol. 1. Metzler. p. 644.Archived(PDF) from the original on 2023-06-12. Retrieved2018-05-04.
  7. ^Toepfer, G."Function".BioConcepts: The Origin and Definition of Biological Concepts. Das Zentrum für Literatur- und Kulturforschung Berlin. Archived fromthe original on 12 June 2023. Retrieved4 May 2018.
  8. ^ab"Understanding Evolution: Qualifying as an adaptation". University of California at Berkeley.Archived from the original on 7 November 2017. Retrieved29 July 2016.
  9. ^abZimmer, Carl;Emlen, Douglas J. (2013).Evolution: Making Sense of Life (1st ed.). Roberts and Company Publishers.ISBN 978-1-936221-17-2.
  10. ^abHladký, V.; Havlíček, J. (2013)."Was Tinbergen an Aristotelian? Comparison of Tinbergen's Four Whys and Aristotle's Four Causes"(PDF).Human Ethology Bulletin.28 (4):3–11.Archived(PDF) from the original on 2017-04-04. Retrieved2017-04-05.
  11. ^abcd"Teleological Notions in Biology".Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 18 May 2003.Archived from the original on 13 March 2020. Retrieved28 July 2016.
  12. ^Hall, Brian K.; Hallgrímsson, Benedikt (2008).Strickberger's Evolution (4th ed.). Jones and Bartlett. pp. 4–6.ISBN 9781449647223.
  13. ^Carter, J. Stein (1996)."Photosynthesis".University of Cincinnati. Archived fromthe original on 2013-06-29.
  14. ^Shih, Patrick M. (2015)."Photosynthesis and early Earth".Current Biology.25 (19):R855 –R859.doi:10.1016/j.cub.2015.04.046.PMID 26439346.Photosynthesis has been instrumental in the success of life on Earth
  15. ^"Sociobiology". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 11 November 2013.Archived from the original on 7 August 2019. Retrieved4 April 2017.
  16. ^Tinbergen, N. (1963). "On aims and methods of Ethology".Zeitschrift für Tierpsychologie.20 (4):410–433.doi:10.1111/j.1439-0310.1963.tb01161.x.
  17. ^"The Four Areas of Biology"(PDF). Archived fromthe original(PDF) on 18 January 2012. Retrieved2 September 2018.
  18. ^"The Four Areas of Biology".Archived from the original on 14 May 2017. Retrieved2 September 2018.
  19. ^Caro, TM (1986). "The functions of stotting in Thomson's gazelles: Some tests of the predictions".Animal Behaviour.34 (3):663–684.doi:10.1016/S0003-3472(86)80052-5.S2CID 53155678.
  20. ^abCummins, Robert (1975). "Functional Analysis".The Journal of Philosophy.72 (20):741–765.doi:10.2307/2024640.JSTOR 2024640.
  21. ^abMillikan, Ruth (1989)."In Defense of Proper Functions".Philosophy of Science.56 (2):288–302.doi:10.1086/289488.JSTOR 187875.S2CID 120910145.
  22. ^abBoorse, Christopher (1977). "Health as a Theoretical Concept".Philosophy of Science.44 (4):542–573.CiteSeerX 10.1.1.486.2236.doi:10.1086/288768.JSTOR 186939.S2CID 146325798.
  23. ^Amundson, Ron; Lauder, George (1994). "Function Without Purpose".Biology and Philosophy.9 (4):443–469.doi:10.1007/BF00850375.S2CID 4997676.
  24. ^Craver, Carl F. (2001). "Role Functions, Mechanisms, and Hierarchy".Philosophy of Science.68 (1):53–74.doi:10.1086/392866.JSTOR 3081024.S2CID 35230404.
  25. ^Neander, Karen (1991). "Functions as Selected Effects: The Conceptual Analyst's Defense".Philosophy of Science.58 (2):168–184.doi:10.1086/289610.JSTOR 187457.S2CID 122866072.
  26. ^Bigelow, John; Pargetter, Robert (1987). "Functions".The Journal of Philosophy.84 (4):181–196.doi:10.2307/2027157.JSTOR 2027157.
Biology
Overview
Chemical basis
Cells
Genetics
Evolution
Diversity
Plant form
and function
Animal form
and function
Ecology
Research
methods
Laboratory
techniques
Field techniques
Branches
Glossaries
Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Function_(biology)&oldid=1236617538"
Category:
Hidden categories:

[8]ページ先頭

©2009-2025 Movatter.jp