Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


Jump to content
WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
Search

Cardinality

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Size of a set
For other uses, seeCardinality (disambiguation).
The setS{\displaystyle S} of allPlatonic solids has 5 elements. Thus the cardinality ofS{\displaystyle S} is 5 or, written symbolically,|S|=5{\displaystyle |S|=5}.

Inmathematics, thecardinality of aset is the number of its elements. The cardinality of a set may also be called itssize, when no confusion with other notions of size is possible.[a] Beginning in the late 19th century, this concept of size was generalized toinfinite sets, allowing one to distinguish between different types of infinity and to performarithmetic on them. Nowadays, infinite sets are encountered in almost all parts of mathematics, even those that may seem to be unrelated. Familiar examples are provided by mostnumber systems andalgebraic structures (natural numbers,rational numbers,real numbers,vector spaces, etc.), as well as, in geometry, bylines,line segments andcurves, which are considered as the sets of their points.

There are two approaches to describing cardinality: one which usescardinal numbers and another which compares sets directly using functions between them, eitherbijections orinjections.The former states the size as a number; the latter compares their relative size and led to the discovery of different sizes of infinity.[1] For example, the setsA={1,2,3}{\displaystyle A=\{1,2,3\}} andB={2,4,6}{\displaystyle B=\{2,4,6\}} are the same size as they each contain 3elements (the first approach) and there is a bijection between them (the second approach).

Etymology

[edit]

In English, the termcardinality originates from thepost-classical Latincardinalis, meaning “principal” or “chief,” which derives fromcardo, a noun meaning “hinge.” In Latin,cardo referred to something central or pivotal, both literally and metaphorically. This concept of centrality passed intomedieval Latin and then into English, wherecardinal came to describe things considered to be, in some sense, fundamental, such ascardinal virtues,cardinal directions, and (in the grammatical sense)cardinal numbers.[2] The last of which referred to numbers used for counting (e.g., one, two, three),[3] as opposed toordinal numbers, which express order (e.g., first, second, third),[4] andnominal numbers used for labeling (without meaning).

In mathematics, the notion of cardinality was first introduced byGeorg Cantor in the late 19th century, wherein he used the used the termMächtigkeit, which may be translated as “magnitude” or “power", though Cantor credited the term to a work byJakob Steiner onprojective geometry.[5][6][7] The termscardinality andcardinal number were eventually adopted from the grammatical sense, and later translations would use these terms.

History

[edit]

Prehistory

[edit]

A crude sense of cardinality, an awareness that groups of things or events compare with other groups by containing more, fewer, or the same number of instances, is observed in a variety of present-day animal species, suggesting an origin millions of years ago.[8] Human expression of cardinality is seen as early as40000 years ago, with equating the size of a group with a group of recorded notches, or a representative collection of other things, such as sticks and shells.[9] The abstraction of cardinality as a number is evident by 3000 BCE, in Sumerianmathematics and the manipulation of numbers without reference to a specific group of things or events.[10]

Ancient History

[edit]

From the 6th century BCE, the writings of Greek philosophers show hints of the cardinality of infinite sets. While they considered the notion of infinity as an endless series of actions, such as adding 1 to a number repeatedly, they did not consider the size of an infinite set of numbers to be a thing.[11] The ancient Greek notion of infinity also considered the division of things into parts repeated without limit. In Euclid'sElements,commensurability was described as the ability to compare the length of two line segments,a andb, as a ratio, as long as there were a third segment, no matter how small, that could be laid end-to-end a whole number of times into botha andb. But with the discovery ofirrational numbers, it was seen that even the infinite set of all rational numbers was not enough to describe the length of every possible line segment.[12]

Diagram of Aristotle's wheel as described inMechanica.

One of the earliest explicit uses of a one-to-one correspondence is recorded inAristotle'sMechanics, known asAristotle's wheel paradox. The paradox can be briefly described as follows: A wheel is depicted as twoconcentric circles. The larger, outer circle is tangent to a horizontal line (e.g. a road that it rolls on), while the smaller, inner circle is rigidly affixed to the larger. Assuming the larger circle rolls along the line without slipping (or skidding) for one full revolution, the distances moved by both circles are the same: thecircumference of the larger circle. Further, the lines traced by the bottom-most point of each is the same length.[13] Since the smaller wheel does not skip any points, and no point on the smaller wheel is used more than once, there is a one-to-one correspondence between the two circles.

Pre-Cantorian Set theory

[edit]

Galileo Galilei presented what was later coinedGalileo's paradox in his bookTwo New Sciences (1638), where he attempts to show that infinite quantities cannot be called greater or less than one another. He presents the paradox roughly as follows: asquare number is one which is the product of another number with itself, such as 4 and 9, which are the squares of 2 and 3 respectively. Then thesquare root of a square number is that multiplicand. He then notes that there are as many square numbers as there are square roots, since every square has its own root and every root its own square, while no square has more than one root and no root more than one square. But there are as many square roots as there are numbers, since every number is the square root of some square. He, however, concluded that this meant we could not compare the sizes of infinite sets, missing the opportunity to discover cardinality.[14]

Bernard Bolzano'sParadoxes of the Infinite (Paradoxien des Unendlichen, 1851) is generally considered the first rigorous introduction of sets to mathematics. In his work, he (among other things) expanded on Galileo's paradox, and introduced one-to-one correspondence of infinite sets, for example between theintervals[0,5]{\displaystyle [0,5]} and[0,12]{\displaystyle [0,12]} by the relation5y=12x{\displaystyle 5y=12x}. However, he resisted saying these sets wereequinumerous, and his work is generally considered to have been uninfluential in mathematics of his time.[15][16]

Early Set theory

[edit]

To better understand infinite sets, a notion of cardinality was formulatedc. 1880 byGeorg Cantor, the originator ofset theory. He examined the process of equating two sets with abijection, a one-to-one correspondence between the elements of two sets. In 1891, with the publication ofhis diagonal argument, he demonstrated that there are sets of numbers that cannot be placed in one-to-one correspondence with the set of natural numbers, i.e., there are "uncountable sets" that contain more elements than there are in the infinite set of natural numbers.[17]

Notation and terminology

[edit]

The cardinality, orcardinal number, of a setA{\displaystyle A} is generally denoted by|A|{\displaystyle |A|}, with avertical bar on each side.[18] (This is the same notation as forabsolute value; the meaning depends on context.) The notation|A|=|B|{\displaystyle |A|=|B|} means that the two setsA{\displaystyle A} andB{\displaystyle B} have the same cardinality. The cardinal number of a setA{\displaystyle A} may also be denoted byn(A){\displaystyle n(A)},A{\displaystyle A},card(A){\displaystyle \operatorname {card} (A)},#A{\displaystyle \#A}, etc.It is conventional to recognize three kinds of cardinality:

Comparing sets

[edit]
A one-to-one correspondence fromN, the set of all non-negative integers, to the setE of non-negativeeven numbers. AlthoughE is a proper subset ofN, both sets have the same cardinality.
N does not have the same cardinality as itspower setP(N): For every functionf fromN toP(N), the setT = {nN:nf(n)} disagrees with every set in therange off, hencef cannot be surjective. The picture shows an examplef and the correspondingT;red:nf(n)\T,blue:nT\f(n).

While the cardinality of a finite set is simply its number of elements, extending that notion to infinite sets usually starts with defining comparison of sizes of arbitrary sets (some of which are possibly infinite).

Definition 1: |A| = |B|

[edit]

Two sets have the same cardinality if there exists a one-to-one correspondence between the elements ofA{\displaystyle A} and thoseB{\displaystyle B} (that is, abijection fromA{\displaystyle A} toB{\displaystyle B}).[19] Such sets are said to beequipotent,equipollent, orequinumerous.

For example, the setE={0,2,4,6,...}{\displaystyle E=\{0,2,4,6,{\text{...}}\}} of non-negativeeven numbers has the same cardinality as the setN={0,1,2,3,...}{\displaystyle \mathbb {N} =\{0,1,2,3,{\text{...}}\}} ofnatural numbers, since the functionf(n)=2n{\displaystyle f(n)=2n} is a bijection fromN{\displaystyle \mathbb {N} } toE{\displaystyle E} (see picture).

For finite setsA{\displaystyle A} andB{\displaystyle B}, ifsome bijection exists fromA{\displaystyle A} toB{\displaystyle B}, theneach injective or surjective function fromA{\displaystyle A} toB{\displaystyle B} is a bijection. This is no longer true for infiniteA{\displaystyle A} andB{\displaystyle B}. For example, the functiong{\displaystyle g} fromN{\displaystyle \mathbb {N} } toE{\displaystyle E}, defined byg(n)=4n{\displaystyle g(n)=4n} is injective, but not surjective since 2, for instance, is not mapped to, andh{\displaystyle h} fromN{\displaystyle \mathbb {N} } toE{\displaystyle E}, defined byh(n)=n(n mod 2){\displaystyle h(n)=n-(n{\text{ mod }}2)} (see:modulo operation) is surjective, but not injective, since 0 and 1 for instance both map to 0. Neitherg{\displaystyle g} norh{\displaystyle h} can challenge|E|=|N|{\displaystyle |E|=|\mathbb {N} |}, which was established by the existence off{\displaystyle f}.

Definition 2: |A| ≤ |B|

[edit]

A{\displaystyle A} has cardinality less than or equal to the cardinality ofB{\displaystyle B}, if there exists an injective function fromA{\displaystyle A} intoB{\displaystyle B}.

If|A||B|{\displaystyle |A|\leq |B|} and|B||A|{\displaystyle |B|\leq |A|}, then|A|=|B|{\displaystyle |A|=|B|} (a fact known as theSchröder–Bernstein theorem). Theaxiom of choice is equivalent to the statement that|A||B|{\displaystyle |A|\leq |B|} or|B||A|{\displaystyle |B|\leq |A|} for everyA{\displaystyle A} andB{\displaystyle B}.[20][21]

Definition 3: |A| < |B|

[edit]

A{\displaystyle A} has cardinality strictly less than the cardinality ofB{\displaystyle B}, if there is an injective function, but no bijective function, fromA{\displaystyle A} toB{\displaystyle B}.

For example, the setN{\displaystyle \mathbb {N} } of allnatural numbers has cardinality strictly less than itspower setP(N){\displaystyle {\mathcal {P}}(\mathbb {N} )}, becauseg(n)={n}{\displaystyle g(n)=\{n\}} is an injective function fromN{\displaystyle \mathbb {N} } toP(N){\displaystyle {\mathcal {P}}(\mathbb {N} )}, and it can be shown that no function fromN{\displaystyle \mathbb {N} } toP(N){\displaystyle {\mathcal {P}}(\mathbb {N} )} can be bijective (see picture). By a similar argument,N{\displaystyle \mathbb {N} } has cardinality strictly less than the cardinality of the setR{\displaystyle \mathbb {R} } of allreal numbers. For proofs, seeCantor's diagonal argument orCantor's first uncountability proof.

Cardinal numbers

[edit]
Main article:Cardinal number

In the above section, "cardinality" of a set was defined functionally. In other words, it was not defined as a specific object itself. However, such an object can be defined as follows.

The relation of having the same cardinality is calledequinumerosity, and this is anequivalence relation on theclass of all sets. Theequivalence class of a setA under this relation, then, consists of all those sets which have the same cardinality asA. There are two ways to define the "cardinality of a set":

  1. The cardinality of a setA is defined as its equivalence class under equinumerosity.
  2. Arepresentative set is designated for each equivalence class. The most common choice is theinitial ordinal in that class. This is usually taken as the definition ofcardinal number inaxiomatic set theory.

Assuming theaxiom of choice, the cardinalities of theinfinite sets are denoted

0<1<2<.{\displaystyle \aleph _{0}<\aleph _{1}<\aleph _{2}<\ldots .}

For eachordinalα{\displaystyle \alpha },α+1{\displaystyle \aleph _{\alpha +1}} is the least cardinal number greater thanα{\displaystyle \aleph _{\alpha }}.

The cardinality of thenatural numbers is denotedaleph-null (0{\displaystyle \aleph _{0}}), while the cardinality of thereal numbers is denoted by "c{\displaystyle {\mathfrak {c}}}" (a lowercasefraktur script "c"), and is also referred to as thecardinality of the continuum. Cantor showed, using thediagonal argument, thatc>0{\displaystyle {\mathfrak {c}}>\aleph _{0}}. We can show thatc=20{\displaystyle {\mathfrak {c}}=2^{\aleph _{0}}}, this also being the cardinality of the set of all subsets of the natural numbers.

Thecontinuum hypothesis says that1=20{\displaystyle \aleph _{1}=2^{\aleph _{0}}}, i.e.20{\displaystyle 2^{\aleph _{0}}} is the smallest cardinal number bigger than0{\displaystyle \aleph _{0}}, i.e. there is no set whose cardinality is strictly between that of the integers and that of the real numbers. The continuum hypothesis isindependent ofZFC, a standard axiomatization of set theory; that is, it is impossible to prove the continuum hypothesis or its negation from ZFC—provided that ZFC is consistent. For more detail, see§ Cardinality of the continuum below.[22][23][24]

Infinite sets

[edit]

Our intuition gained fromfinite sets breaks down when dealing withinfinite sets. In the late 19th centuryGeorg Cantor,Gottlob Frege,Richard Dedekind and others rejected the view that the whole cannot be the same size as the part.[25][citation needed] One example of this isHilbert's paradox of the Grand Hotel.Indeed, Dedekind defined an infinite set as one that can be placed into a one-to-one correspondence with a strict subset (that is, having the same size in Cantor's sense); this notion of infinity is calledDedekind infinite. Cantor introduced the cardinal numbers, and showed—according to his bijection-based definition of size—that some infinite sets are greater than others. The smallest infinite cardinality is that of the natural numbers (0{\displaystyle \aleph _{0}}).

Cardinality of the continuum

[edit]
Main article:Cardinality of the continuum

One of Cantor's most important results was that thecardinality of the continuum (c{\displaystyle {\mathfrak {c}}}) is greater than that of the natural numbers (0{\displaystyle \aleph _{0}}); that is, there are more real numbersR than natural numbersN. Namely, Cantor showed thatc=20=1{\displaystyle {\mathfrak {c}}=2^{\aleph _{0}}=\beth _{1}} (seeBeth one) satisfies:

20>0{\displaystyle 2^{\aleph _{0}}>\aleph _{0}}
(seeCantor's diagonal argument orCantor's first uncountability proof).

Thecontinuum hypothesis states that there is nocardinal number between the cardinality of the reals and the cardinality of the natural numbers, that is,

20=1{\displaystyle 2^{\aleph _{0}}=\aleph _{1}}

However, this hypothesis can neither be proved nor disproved within the widely acceptedZFCaxiomatic set theory, if ZFC is consistent.

Cardinal arithmetic can be used to show not only that the number of points in areal number line is equal to the number of points in anysegment of that line, but that this is equal to the number of points on a plane and, indeed, in any finite-dimensional space. These results are highly counterintuitive, because they imply that there existproper subsets andproper supersets of an infinite setS that have the same size asS, althoughS contains elements that do not belong to its subsets, and the supersets ofS contain elements that are not included in it.

The first of these results is apparent by considering, for instance, thetangent function, which provides aone-to-one correspondence between theinterval (−½π, ½π) andR (see alsoHilbert's paradox of the Grand Hotel).

The second result was first demonstrated by Cantor in 1878, but it became more apparent in 1890, whenGiuseppe Peano introduced thespace-filling curves, curved lines that twist and turn enough to fill the whole of any square, or cube, orhypercube, or finite-dimensional space. These curves are not a direct proof that a line has the same number of points as a finite-dimensional space, but they can be used to obtainsuch a proof.

Cantor also showed that sets with cardinality strictly greater thanc{\displaystyle {\mathfrak {c}}} exist (see hisgeneralized diagonal argument andtheorem). They include, for instance:

  • the set of all subsets ofR, i.e., thepower set ofR, writtenP(R) or 2R
  • the setRR of all functions fromR toR

Both have cardinality

2c=2>c{\displaystyle 2^{\mathfrak {c}}=\beth _{2}>{\mathfrak {c}}}
(seeBeth two).

Thecardinal equalitiesc2=c,{\displaystyle {\mathfrak {c}}^{2}={\mathfrak {c}},}c0=c,{\displaystyle {\mathfrak {c}}^{\aleph _{0}}={\mathfrak {c}},} andcc=2c{\displaystyle {\mathfrak {c}}^{\mathfrak {c}}=2^{\mathfrak {c}}} can be demonstrated usingcardinal arithmetic:

c2=(20)2=22×0=20=c,{\displaystyle {\mathfrak {c}}^{2}=\left(2^{\aleph _{0}}\right)^{2}=2^{2\times {\aleph _{0}}}=2^{\aleph _{0}}={\mathfrak {c}},}
c0=(20)0=20×0=20=c,{\displaystyle {\mathfrak {c}}^{\aleph _{0}}=\left(2^{\aleph _{0}}\right)^{\aleph _{0}}=2^{{\aleph _{0}}\times {\aleph _{0}}}=2^{\aleph _{0}}={\mathfrak {c}},}
cc=(20)c=2c×0=2c.{\displaystyle {\mathfrak {c}}^{\mathfrak {c}}=\left(2^{\aleph _{0}}\right)^{\mathfrak {c}}=2^{{\mathfrak {c}}\times \aleph _{0}}=2^{\mathfrak {c}}.}

Examples and properties

[edit]
  • IfX = {a,b,c} andY = {apples, oranges, peaches}, wherea,b, andc are distinct, then | X | = | Y | because { (a, apples), (b, oranges), (c, peaches)} is a bijection between the setsX andY. The cardinality of each ofX andY is 3.
  • If | X | ≤ | Y |, then there existsZ such that | X | = | Z | andZY.
  • If | X | ≤ | Y | and | Y | ≤ | X |, then | X | = | Y |. This holds even for infinite cardinals, and is known asCantor–Bernstein–Schroeder theorem.
  • Sets with cardinality of the continuum include the set of all real numbers, the set of allirrational numbers and the interval[0,1]{\displaystyle [0,1]}.

Union and intersection

[edit]
Main article:Inclusion-exclusion principle

IfA andB aredisjoint sets, then

|AB|=|A|+|B|.{\displaystyle \left\vert A\cup B\right\vert =\left\vert A\right\vert +\left\vert B\right\vert .}

From this, one can show that in general, the cardinalities ofunions andintersections are related by the following equation:[26]

|CD|+|CD|=|C|+|D|.{\displaystyle \left\vert C\cup D\right\vert +\left\vert C\cap D\right\vert =\left\vert C\right\vert +\left\vert D\right\vert .}

Definition of cardinality in class theory (NBG orMK)

[edit]

HereV{\displaystyle V} denote a class of all sets, andOrd{\displaystyle {\mbox{Ord}}} denotes the class of all ordinal numbers.

|A|:=Ord{αOrd|(f:Aα):(f injective)}{\displaystyle |A|:={\mbox{Ord}}\cap \bigcap \{\alpha \in {\mbox{Ord}}|\exists (f:A\to \alpha ):(f{\mbox{ injective}})\}}

We use the intersection of a class which is defined by(xQ)(qQ:xq){\displaystyle (x\in \bigcap Q)\iff (\forall q\in Q:x\in q)}, therefore=V{\displaystyle \bigcap \emptyset =V}.In this case

(x|x|):VOrd{\displaystyle (x\mapsto |x|):V\to {\mbox{Ord}}}.

This definition allows also obtain a cardinality of any proper classP{\displaystyle P}, in particular

|P|=Ord{\displaystyle |P|={\mbox{Ord}}}

This definition is natural since it agrees with the axiom of limitation of size which implies bijection betweenV{\displaystyle V} and any proper class.

See also

[edit]
Wikimedia Commons has media related toCardinality.

References

[edit]

Citations

[edit]
  1. ^Stoll, Robert R. (1963).Set Theory and Logic. San Francisco, CA: Dover Publications.ISBN 978-0-486-63829-4.
  2. ^Oxford English Dictionary, “cardinal (adj.), Etymology,” March 2025,https://doi.org/10.1093/OED/1490074521.
  3. ^Oxford English Dictionary, “cardinal number (n.), sense 1,” July 2023,https://doi.org/10.1093/OED/3193437451.
  4. ^Oxford English Dictionary, “ordinal (n.2),” June 2024,https://doi.org/10.1093/OED/6032173309.
  5. ^Ferreirós, José (2007).Labyrinth of Thought (2nd ed.). Basel:Birkhäuser. p. 24.doi:10.1007/978-3-7643-8350-3.ISBN 978-3-7643-8349-7.
  6. ^Cantor, Georg (1932).Zermelo, Ernst (ed.)."Gesammelte Abhandlungen".Springer. Berlin: Springer: 151.doi:10.1007/978-3-662-00274-2.ISBN 978-3-662-00254-4.
  7. ^Steiner, Jacob (1867).Vorlesungen über synthetische Geometrie / 1 Die Theorie der Kegelschnitte in elementarer Form. Ghent University. Leipzig : Teubner.
  8. ^Cepelewicz, JordanaAnimals Count and Use Zero. How Far Does Their Number Sense Go?,Quanta, August 9, 2021
  9. ^"Early Human Counting Tools".Math Timeline. Retrieved2018-04-26.
  10. ^Duncan J. Melville (2003).Third Millennium ChronologyArchived 2018-07-07 at theWayback Machine,Third Millennium Mathematics.St. Lawrence University.
  11. ^Allen, Donald (2003)."The History of Infinity"(PDF).Texas A&M Mathematics. Archived fromthe original(PDF) on August 1, 2020. RetrievedNov 15, 2019.
  12. ^Kurt Von Fritz (1945). "The Discovery of Incommensurability by Hippasus of Metapontum".The Annals of Mathematics.
  13. ^Drabkin, Israel E. (1950). "Aristotle's Wheel: Notes on the History of a Paradox".Osiris.9:162–198.doi:10.1086/368528.JSTOR 301848.S2CID 144387607.
  14. ^Galilei, Galileo (1914) [1638].Dialogues Concerning Two New Sciences(PDF). Translated by Crew, Henry; De Salvio, Alfonso. New York:The Macmillan Company. pp. 31–33.
  15. ^Ferreirós, José (2024),"The Early Development of Set Theory", in Zalta, Edward N.; Nodelman, Uri (eds.),The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2024 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University,archived from the original on 2021-05-12, retrieved2025-01-04
  16. ^Bolzano, Bernard (1975), Berg, Jan (ed.),Einleitung zur Größenlehre und erste Begriffe der allgemeinen Größenlehre, Bernard-Bolzano-Gesamtausgabe, edited by Eduard Winter et al., vol. II, A, 7, Stuttgart, Bad Cannstatt: Friedrich Frommann Verlag, p. 152,ISBN 3-7728-0466-7
  17. ^Georg Cantor (1891)."Ueber eine elementare Frage der Mannigfaltigkeitslehre"(PDF).Jahresbericht der Deutschen Mathematiker-Vereinigung.1:75–78.
  18. ^"Cardinality | Brilliant Math & Science Wiki".brilliant.org. Retrieved2020-08-23.
  19. ^ab"Infinite Sets and Cardinality".Mathematics LibreTexts. 2019-12-05. Retrieved2020-08-23.
  20. ^Friedrich M. Hartogs (1915),Felix Klein;Walther von Dyck;David Hilbert;Otto Blumenthal (eds.),"Über das Problem der Wohlordnung",Mathematische Annalen,76 (4), Leipzig: B. G. Teubner:438–443,doi:10.1007/bf01458215,ISSN 0025-5831,S2CID 121598654
  21. ^Felix Hausdorff (2002),Egbert Brieskorn; Srishti D. Chatterji; et al. (eds.),Grundzüge der Mengenlehre (1. ed.), Berlin/Heidelberg: Springer, p. 587,ISBN 3-540-42224-2 -Original edition (1914)
  22. ^Cohen, Paul J. (December 15, 1963)."The Independence of the Continuum Hypothesis".Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America.50 (6):1143–1148.Bibcode:1963PNAS...50.1143C.doi:10.1073/pnas.50.6.1143.JSTOR 71858.PMC 221287.PMID 16578557.
  23. ^Cohen, Paul J. (January 15, 1964)."The Independence of the Continuum Hypothesis, II".Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America.51 (1):105–110.Bibcode:1964PNAS...51..105C.doi:10.1073/pnas.51.1.105.JSTOR 72252.PMC 300611.PMID 16591132.
  24. ^Penrose, R (2005),The Road to Reality: A Complete Guide to the Laws of the Universe, Vintage Books,ISBN 0-09-944068-7
  25. ^Georg Cantor (1887), "Mitteilungen zur Lehre vom Transfiniten",Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik,91:81–125
    Reprinted in:Georg Cantor (1932), Adolf Fraenkel (Lebenslauf); Ernst Zermelo (eds.),Gesammelte Abhandlungen mathematischen und philosophischen Inhalts, Berlin: Springer, pp. 378–439 Here: p.413 bottom
  26. ^Applied Abstract Algebra, K.H. Kim, F.W. Roush, Ellis Horwood Series, 1983,ISBN 0-85312-612-7 (student edition),ISBN 0-85312-563-5 (library edition)
  1. ^Such aslength andarea ingeometry. – A line segment of finite length is a set of points that has infinite cardinality.

Bibliography

[edit]
General
Theorems (list)
 and paradoxes
Logics
Traditional
Propositional
Predicate
Set theory
Types ofsets
Maps and cardinality
Set theories
Formal systems (list),
language and syntax
Example axiomatic
systems
 (list)
Proof theory
Model theory
Computability theory
Related
Overview
Venn diagram of set intersection
Axioms
Operations
  • Concepts
  • Methods
Set types
Theories
Set theorists
Authority control databases: NationalEdit this at Wikidata
Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Cardinality&oldid=1284667893"
Categories:
Hidden categories:

[8]ページ先頭

©2009-2025 Movatter.jp