Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


Jump to content
WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
Search

Alcinous (philosopher)

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
2nd-century Greek philosopher

Alcinous (Greek:ἈλκίνοοςAlkinoos) was aMiddle Platonistphilosopher. He probably lived in the 2nd century AD,[1] although nothing is known about his life.[2] He is the author ofThe Handbook of Platonism, an epitome ofMiddle Platonism intended as a manual for teachers. He has, at times, been identified by some scholars with the 2nd century Middle PlatonistAlbinus.

Writings

[edit]

Alcinous is the author of work calledThe Handbook of Platonism (Ἐπιτομὴ τῶν Πλάτωνος δογμάτων, alsoΔιδασκαλικὸς τῶν Πλάτωνος δογμάτων;Latin:De doctrina Platonis), one of the few surviving works from theMiddle Platonist period (c. 90 BC – 250 AD). The book contains 36 chapters which cover topics ranging from logic to physics to ethics. It is thought to have been intended as a manual, not for students of Platonism, but for its teachers. The treatise is written in the esoteric manner typical of theCorpus Aristotelicum, and it often appropriates popular concepts from other philosophical schools—in particular thePeripatetic andStoic schools—which could be seen as having been prefigured in the works of Plato.

Alcinous's handbook has been dated to the middle of the 2nd century AD.[1] In 1879 the German scholarJacob Freudenthal argued that Alcinous was really the philosopherAlbinus, the teacher ofGalen the physician. This theory remained largely unchallenged until 1974, when John Whittaker made a fresh case convincingly reaffirming Alcinous's authenticity.[3][4]

Alcinous held the world and its animating soul to be eternal.[5] This soul of the universe was not created byGod, but, to use the image of Alcinous, it was awakened by him as from a profound sleep, and turned towards himself, "that it might look out upon intellectual things and receive forms and ideas from the divine mind."[5] It was the first of a succession of intermediate beings between God and man.[6] Theidea proceeded immediately from the mind of God, and were the highest object of our intellect; the "form" of matter, the types of sensible things, having a real being in themselves.[7] He differed from the earlier Platonists in confining theideas to general laws: it seemed an unworthy notion that God could conceive anidea of things artificial or unnatural, or of individuals or particulars, or of any thing relative.[8] He seems to have aimed at harmonizing the views of Plato and Aristotle on theideas, as he distinguished them from theeidos, forms of things, which he allowed were inseparable: a view which seems necessarily connected with the doctrine of the eternity and self-existence of matter.[9] God, the first fountain of theideas, could not be known as he is: it is but a faint notion of him we obtain from negations and analogies: his nature is equally beyond our power of expression or conception.[10] Below him are a series of beings (daimones)[11] who superintend the production of all living things, and hold intercourse with men. The human soul passes through various transmigrations, thus connecting the series with the lower classes of being, until it is finally purified and rendered acceptable to God.[12] His system is understood as a synthesis of Plato and Aristotle, with some elements borrowed from the East, and perhaps derived from a study of thePythagorean system, which experienced arevival of sorts concomitant to that which produced Middle Platonism.

References

[edit]
  1. ^ab"Alcinous fits most comfortably into a period bounded by the writings ofPlutarch on the one hand, andGalen andAlexander of Aphrodisias on the other, withApuleius,Albinus,Atticus,Numenius, the PeripateticAspasius, ... andMaximus of Tyre as approximate contemporaries." John Dillon, 1993,Alcinous, The Handbook of Platonism, page xiii. Oxford.
  2. ^Schmitz, Leonhard (1867)."Alcinous (3)". InWilliam Smith (ed.).Dictionary of Greek and Roman Biography and Mythology. Vol. 1. Boston:Little, Brown and Company. pp. 102–103. Archived from the original on 2007-10-28.
  3. ^John Whittaker, (1974),Parisinus Graecus 1962 and the Writings of Albinus, Phoenix 28, 320–354, 450–456.
  4. ^"Bryn Mawr Classical Review 94.10.14". Archived fromthe original on 2001-05-04. Retrieved2007-10-10.
  5. ^abAlcinous,Handbook, 14.3.
  6. ^Alcinous,Handbook, 14.6–7, 15.1.
  7. ^Alcinous,Handbook, 9.1.
  8. ^Alcinous,Handbook, 9.2.
  9. ^Alcinous,Handbook, 9.3.
  10. ^Alcinous,Handbook, 10.4–6.
  11. ^Alcinous,Handbook, 15.1.
  12. ^Alcinous,Handbook, 16.1–2.

Sources

[edit]

External links

[edit]
Ancient
Academics
Old
Skeptics
Middle
New
Middle Platonists
Neoplatonists
Academy
Medieval
Modern
Renaissance
Florentine Academy
Cambridge
Contemporary
Analytic
Continental


International
National
Academics
People
Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Alcinous_(philosopher)&oldid=1279117731"
Categories:
Hidden categories:

[8]ページ先頭

©2009-2025 Movatter.jp