Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


Jump to content
WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
Search

Regular cardinal

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
(Redirected fromSingular cardinal)
Type of cardinal number in mathematics

Inset theory, aregular cardinal is acardinal number that is equal to its owncofinality. More explicitly, this means thatκ{\displaystyle \kappa } is a regular cardinal if and only if everyunbounded subsetCκ{\displaystyle C\subseteq \kappa } has cardinalityκ{\displaystyle \kappa }. Infinitewell-ordered cardinals that are not regular are calledsingular cardinals. Finite cardinal numbers are typically not called regular or singular.

In the presence of theaxiom of choice, any cardinal number can be well-ordered, and then the following are equivalent for a cardinalκ{\displaystyle \kappa }:

  1. κ{\displaystyle \kappa } is a regular cardinal.
  2. Ifκ=iIλi{\displaystyle \kappa =\sum _{i\in I}\lambda _{i}} andλi<κ{\displaystyle \lambda _{i}<\kappa } for alli{\displaystyle i}, then|I|κ{\displaystyle |I|\geq \kappa }.
  3. IfS=iISi{\displaystyle S=\bigcup _{i\in I}S_{i}}, and if|I|<κ{\displaystyle |I|<\kappa } and|Si|<κ{\displaystyle |S_{i}|<\kappa } for alli{\displaystyle i}, then|S|<κ{\displaystyle |S|<\kappa }. That is, every union of fewer thanκ{\displaystyle \kappa } sets smaller thanκ{\displaystyle \kappa } is smaller thanκ{\displaystyle \kappa }.
  4. ThecategorySet<κ{\displaystyle \operatorname {Set} _{<\kappa }} of sets of cardinality less thanκ{\displaystyle \kappa } and all functions between them is closed undercolimits of cardinality less thanκ{\displaystyle \kappa }.
  5. κ{\displaystyle \kappa } is a regular ordinal (see below).

Crudely speaking, this means that a regular cardinal is one that cannot be broken down into a small number of smaller parts.

The situation is slightly more complicated in contexts where theaxiom of choice might fail, as in that case not all cardinals are necessarily the cardinalities of well-ordered sets. In that case, the above equivalence holds for well-orderable cardinals only.

An infiniteordinalα{\displaystyle \alpha } is aregular ordinal if it is alimit ordinal that is not the limit of a set of smaller ordinals that as a set hasorder type less thanα{\displaystyle \alpha }. A regular ordinal is always aninitial ordinal, though some initial ordinals are not regular, e.g.,ωω{\displaystyle \omega _{\omega }} (see the example below).

Examples

[edit]

The ordinals less thanω{\displaystyle \omega } are finite. A finite sequence of finite ordinals always has a finite maximum, soω{\displaystyle \omega } cannot be the limit of any sequence of type less thanω{\displaystyle \omega } whose elements are ordinals less thanω{\displaystyle \omega }, and is therefore a regular ordinal.0{\displaystyle \aleph _{0}} (aleph-null) is a regular cardinal because its initial ordinal,ω{\displaystyle \omega }, is regular. It can also be seen directly to be regular, as the cardinal sum of a finite number of finite cardinal numbers is itself finite.

ω+1{\displaystyle \omega +1} is thenext ordinal number greater thanω{\displaystyle \omega }. It is singular, since it is not a limit ordinal.ω+ω{\displaystyle \omega +\omega } is the next limit ordinal afterω{\displaystyle \omega }. It can be written as the limit of the sequenceω{\displaystyle \omega },ω+1{\displaystyle \omega +1},ω+2{\displaystyle \omega +2},ω+3{\displaystyle \omega +3}, and so on. This sequence has order typeω{\displaystyle \omega }, soω+ω{\displaystyle \omega +\omega } is the limit of a sequence of type less thanω+ω{\displaystyle \omega +\omega } whose elements are ordinals less thanω+ω{\displaystyle \omega +\omega }; therefore it is singular.

1{\displaystyle \aleph _{1}} is thenext cardinal number greater than0{\displaystyle \aleph _{0}}, so the cardinals less than1{\displaystyle \aleph _{1}} arecountable (finite or denumerable). Assuming the axiom of choice, the union of a countable set of countable sets is itself countable. So1{\displaystyle \aleph _{1}} cannot be written as the sum of a countable set of countable cardinal numbers, and is regular.

ω{\displaystyle \aleph _{\omega }} is the next cardinal number after the sequence0{\displaystyle \aleph _{0}},1{\displaystyle \aleph _{1}},2{\displaystyle \aleph _{2}},3{\displaystyle \aleph _{3}}, and so on. Its initial ordinalωω{\displaystyle \omega _{\omega }} is the limit of the sequenceω{\displaystyle \omega },ω1{\displaystyle \omega _{1}},ω2{\displaystyle \omega _{2}},ω3{\displaystyle \omega _{3}}, and so on, which has order typeω{\displaystyle \omega }, soωω{\displaystyle \omega _{\omega }} is singular, and so isω{\displaystyle \aleph _{\omega }}. Assuming the axiom of choice,ω{\displaystyle \aleph _{\omega }} is the first infinite cardinal that is singular (the first infiniteordinal that is singular isω+1{\displaystyle \omega +1}, and the first infinitelimit ordinal that is singular isω+ω{\displaystyle \omega +\omega }). Proving the existence of singular cardinals requires theaxiom of replacement, and in fact the inability to prove the existence ofω{\displaystyle \aleph _{\omega }} inZermelo set theory is what ledFraenkel to postulate this axiom.[1]

Uncountable (weak)limit cardinals that are also regular are known as (weakly)inaccessible cardinals. They cannot be proved to exist within ZFC, though their existence is not known to be inconsistent with ZFC. Their existence is sometimes taken as an additional axiom. Inaccessible cardinals are necessarilyfixed points of thealeph function, though not all fixed points are regular. For instance, the first fixed point is the limit of theω{\displaystyle \omega }-sequence0,ω,ωω,...{\displaystyle \aleph _{0},\aleph _{\omega },\aleph _{\omega _{\omega }},...} and is therefore singular.

Properties

[edit]

If theaxiom of choice holds, then everysuccessor cardinal is regular. Thus the regularity or singularity of most aleph numbers can be checked depending on whether the cardinal is a successor cardinal or a limit cardinal. Some cardinalities cannot be proven to be equal to any particular aleph, for instance thecardinality of the continuum, whose value in ZFC may be any uncountable cardinal of uncountable cofinality (seeEaston's theorem). Thecontinuum hypothesis postulates that the cardinality of the continuum is equal to1{\displaystyle \aleph _{1}}, which is regular assuming choice.

Without the axiom of choice: there would be cardinal numbers that were not well-orderable.[citation needed] Moreover, the cardinal sum of an arbitrary collection could not be defined.[citation needed] Therefore, only thealeph numbers could meaningfully be called regular or singular cardinals.[citation needed]Furthermore, a successor aleph would need not be regular. For instance, the union of a countable set of countable sets would not necessarily be countable. It is consistent withZF thatω1{\displaystyle \omega _{1}} be the limit of a countable sequence of countable ordinals as well as the set ofreal numbers be a countable union of countable sets.[citation needed] Furthermore, it is consistent with ZF when not including AC that every aleph bigger than0{\displaystyle \aleph _{0}} is singular (a result proved byMoti Gitik).

Ifκ{\displaystyle \kappa } is a limit ordinal,κ{\displaystyle \kappa } is regular iff the set ofα<κ{\displaystyle \alpha <\kappa } that are critical points ofΣ1{\displaystyle \Sigma _{1}}-elementary embeddingsj{\displaystyle j} withj(α)=κ{\displaystyle j(\alpha )=\kappa } isclub inκ{\displaystyle \kappa }.[2]

For cardinalsκ<θ{\displaystyle \kappa <\theta }, say that an elementary embeddingj:MH(θ){\displaystyle j:M\to H(\theta )} asmall embedding ifM{\displaystyle M} is transitive andj(crit(j))=κ{\displaystyle j({\textrm {crit}}(j))=\kappa }. A cardinalκ{\displaystyle \kappa } is uncountable and regular iff there is anα>κ{\displaystyle \alpha >\kappa } such that for everyθ>α{\displaystyle \theta >\alpha }, there is a small embeddingj:MH(θ){\displaystyle j:M\to H(\theta )}.[3]Corollary 2.2

See also

[edit]

References

[edit]
  1. ^Maddy, Penelope (1988), "Believing the axioms. I",Journal of Symbolic Logic,53 (2):481–511,doi:10.2307/2274520,JSTOR 2274520,MR 0947855,Early hints of the Axiom of Replacement can be found in Cantor's letter to Dedekind [1899] and in Mirimanoff [1917]. Maddy cites two papers by Mirimanoff, "Les antinomies de Russell et de Burali-Forti et le problème fundamental de la théorie des ensembles" and "Remarques sur la théorie des ensembles et les antinomies Cantorienne", both inL'Enseignement Mathématique (1917).
  2. ^T. Arai, "Bounds on provability in set theories" (2012, p.2). Accessed 4 August 2022.
  3. ^Holy, Lücke, Njegomir, "Small embedding characterizations for large cardinals". Annals of Pure and Applied Logic vol. 170, no. 2 (2019), pp.251--271.
General
Theorems (list)
 and paradoxes
Logics
Traditional
Propositional
Predicate
Set theory
Types ofsets
Maps and cardinality
Set theories
Formal systems (list),
language and syntax
Example axiomatic
systems
 (list)
Proof theory
Model theory
Computability theory
Related
Overview
Venn diagram of set intersection
Axioms
Operations
  • Concepts
  • Methods
Set types
Theories
Set theorists
Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Regular_cardinal&oldid=1268210455"
Categories:
Hidden categories:

[8]ページ先頭

©2009-2025 Movatter.jp