A jointPolitics andEconomics series |
Social choice andelectoral systems |
---|
![]() |
Single vote -plurality methods |
By results of combination By mechanism of combination By ballot type |
![]() |
Ranked voting is anyvoting system that uses voters'rankings of candidates to choose a single winner or multiple winners. More formally, a ranked system is one that depends only on which of two candidates is preferred by a voter, and as such does not incorporate any information aboutintensity of preferences. Ranked voting systems vary dramatically in how preferences are tabulated and counted, which gives themvery different properties. Ininstant-runoff voting (IRV) and thesingle transferable vote system (STV), lower preferences are used as contingencies (back-up preferences) and are only applied when all higher-ranked preferences on a ballot have been eliminated or when the vote has been cast for a candidate who has been elected and surplus votes need to be transferred.
Some ranked vote systems use ranks as weights; this type of system is calledpositional voting. In theBorda method, the 1st, 2nd, 3rd... candidates on each ballot receive1, 2, 3... points, and the candidate with the fewest points is elected. Thus intensity of preference is assumed to be at ratios of 1 to 2, 2 to 3, etc. Although not typically described as such, the well-knownplurality rule can be seen as a ranked voting system where a voter gives a single point to the candidate marked as their choice and zero points to all others, and the candidate with the most points is elected. Taking the ranked ballots of instant-runoff voting and the single transferable vote system as indicating one choice at a time (that is, giving one point to the preference in use and zero points to all others), instant-runoff voting can be seen as a non-degenerate ranked voting systems. It operates as a staged variant of the plurality system that repeatedly eliminate last-place plurality winners if necessary to determine a majority winner.[1]
In the United States and Australia, the termsranked-choice voting andpreferential voting, respectively, almost always refer toinstant-runoff voting; however, because these terms have also been used to mean ranked systems in general, manysocial choice theorists recommend the use ofinstant-runoff voting in contexts where it could cause confusion. Ranked voting systems, such as Borda count, are usually contrasted withrated voting methods, which allow voters to indicatehow strongly they support different candidates (e.g. on a scale from 0 to 10).[2] Ranked vote systems produce more information than X voting systems such asfirst-past-the-post voting. Rated voting systems produce more information than ordinal ballots; as a result, some common results likeArrow's theorem do not directly apply to them.[3]
The earliest known proposals for a ranked voting system can be traced to the works ofRamon Llull in the late 13th century, who developed what would later be known asCopeland's method, which is similar toCondorcet's method. Copeland's method was devised byRamon Llull in his 1299 treatiseArs Electionis, which was discussed byNicholas of Cusa in the fifteenth century.[4][5]
A second wave of analysis began whenJean-Charles de Borda published a paper in 1781, advocating for theBorda count, which he called the "order of merit". This methodology drew criticism from theMarquis de Condorcet, who developedhis own methods after arguing Borda's approach did not accurately reflect group preferences, because it was vulnerable tospoiler effects and did not always elect themajority-preferred candidate.[4]
Interest in ranked voting continued throughout the 19th century.Carl Andræ formulated a version of thesingle transferable vote election system, which was adopted by his country,Denmark, in 1855. This used contingent ranked votes to transfer votes of eliminated un-popular candidates but did not include transfers of eliminated candidates.[6][7]
In the 1700s, Condorcet considered a single-winner version of STV, theinstant-runoff system, but rejected it aspathological. In 1864, Edward J. Nanson, while noting Condorcet's concerns, said the IRV method is "a perfectly feasible and practicable one for elections on any scale".[8][9]
Professor W.R. Ware held a demonstration STV election in 1871, by having 150 M.I.T. students elect four English authors as their favorites. The field of candidates held the names of 35 authors in the first count, and eventually concentrated a large proportion of the votes behind just four. Ware went on to surmise how a casual vacancy might be handled and found that countback would produce a winner. This proved that ranked transferable votes could be used to produce a single winner, despite the qualms of Condorcet and others.[10]
Single transferable voting (multi-seat contests using contingent ranked transferable votes) later found common use in cities and to elect legislators in North America, Ireland and other parts of the English-speaking world, with single-winner versions, alternative voting (now known asinstant-runoff voting) andcontingent voting (also known as supplementary voting), being its companions for single-winner contests of mayors and others.[11]
Theoretical exploration of electoral processes was revived by a 1948 paper fromDuncan Black[12] andKenneth Arrow's investigations intosocial choice theory, a branch ofwelfare economics that extendsrational choice to include community decision-making processes.[13]
Plurality voting is the most common voting system, and has been in widespread use since the earliestdemocracies. Asplurality voting has exhibited weaknesses from its start, especially as soon as a third party joins the race, some individuals turned to transferable votes (facilitated by contingent ranked ballots) to reduce the incidence of wasted votes and unrepresentative election results.[14][citation needed]
A form of thesingle transferable vote system was invented byCarl Andræ in Denmark, where it was used briefly before being abandoned in favour ofopen list list PR, but still carried on for indirect election of theupper house until 1953.[citation needed]
At approximately the same time, the single transferable vote system was independently devised by British lawyerThomas Hare, whose writings soon spread the method throughout theBritish Empire.Tasmania used STV (called the Hare system) in government elections in the 1890s. STV began permanent and wider adoption throughout Australia beginning in 1907 and the 1910s.[15] The single transferable vote system, using contingent ranked votes, has been adopted in Ireland, South Africa, Malta, and approximately 40 citiesin the United States and Canada.[16] The single transferable vote system has also been used to elect legislators in Canada, South Africa and India.
In more recent years, the use of contingent ranked votes has seen a comebackin the United States. Single-winner ranked voting (specificallyinstant-runoff voting), is used to elect politicians in Maine[17] and Alaska.[18] In November 2016, the voters ofMaine narrowly passed Question 5, approving ranked-choice voting (instant-runoff voting) for all elections. This was first put to use in 2018, marking the inaugural use of ranked votes in a statewide election in the United States (when Maine's statewide vote tally was used to determine the two at-large electoral college seats).
In November 2020,Alaska voters passed Measure 2, bringing ranked choice voting (instant-runoff voting) into effect from 2022.[19][20] After a series ofelectoral pathologies in Alaska's2022 congressional special election, a poll found 54% of Alaskans supported a repeal of the system. This included a third of the voters who had supportedPeltola, the ultimate winner in the election. However, a referendum on the issue in 2024 saw a narrow majority in favour of retention of IRV.[21][22]
Somelocal elections in New Zealand and in the U.S. use the multi-winnersingle transferable vote.[23][24] STV is also used to elect local authorities in Scotland[25] and Ireland.[26] Nauru uses a rank-weightedpositional method called theDowdall system.
Invoting with ranked ballots, atied orequal-rank ballot is one where multiple candidates receive the same rank or rating. Ininstant runoff andfirst-preference plurality, such ballots are generally rejected; however, insocial choice theory some election systems assume equal-ranked ballots are "split" evenly between all equal-ranked candidates (e.g. in a two-way tie, each candidate receives half a vote). Meanwhile, other election systems, theBorda count and theCondorcet method, can use different rules for handling equal-rank ballots. These rules produce different mathematical properties and behaviors, particularly understrategic voting.
Many concepts formulated by theMarquis de Condorcet in the 18th century continue to significantly impact the field. One of these concepts is theCondorcet winner, a candidate who would win against any other candidate in a two-way race. A voting system that always elects this candidate is called aCondorcet method; however, it is possible for an election to have no Condorcet winner, a situation called aCondorcet cycle. Suppose an election with 3 candidatesA,B, andC has 3 voters. One votesA >C >B, one votesB >A >C, and one votesC >B >A. In this case, no Condorcet winner exists:A cannot be a Condorcet winner as two-thirds of voters preferB overA. Similarly,B cannot be the winner as two-thirds preferC overB, andC cannot win as two-thirds preferA overC. This forms arock-paper-scissors style cycle with no Condorcet winner.
Voting systems can also be judged on their ability to deliver results that maximize the overallwell-being of society, i.e. to choose the best candidate for society as a whole.[27]
Spatial voting models, initially proposed byDuncan Black and further developed byAnthony Downs, provide a theoretical framework for understanding electoral behavior. In these models, each voter and candidate is positioned within an ideological space that can span multiple dimensions. It is assumed that voters tend to favor candidates who closely align with their ideological position over those more distant. Apolitical spectrum is an example of a one-dimensional spatial model.
The accompanying diagram presents a simple one-dimensional spatial model, illustrating the voting methods discussed in subsequent sections of this article. It is assumed that supporters of candidateA cast their votes in the order ofA >B >C, while candidateC's supporters vote in the sequence ofC >B >A. Supporters of candidateB are equally divided between listingA orC as their second preference. From the data in the accompanying table, if there are 100 voters, the distribution of ballots will reflect the positioning of voters and candidates along the ideological spectrum.
Spatial models offer significant insights because they provide an intuitive visualization of voter preferences. These models give rise to an influential theorem—the median voter theorem—attributed to Duncan Black. This theorem stipulates that within a broad range of spatial models, including all one-dimensional models and all symmetric models across multiple dimensions, a Condorcet winner is guaranteed to exist. Moreover, this winner is the candidate closest to the median of the voter distribution. Empirical research has generally found that spatial voting models give a highly accurate explanation of most voting behavior.[28]
Arrow's impossibility theorem is a generalization of Condorcet's result on the impossibility of majority rule. It demonstrates that every ranked voting algorithm is susceptible to thespoiler effect.Gibbard's theorem provides a closely-related corollary, that no voting rule can have a single, always-best strategy that does not depend on other voters' ballots.
The Borda count is a weighted-rank system that assigns scores to each candidate based on their position in each ballot. Ifm is the total number of candidates, the candidate ranked first on a ballot receivesm − 1 points, the second receivesm − 2, and so on, until the last-ranked candidate who receives zero. In the given example, candidateB emerges as the winner with 130 out of a total 300 points. While the Borda count is simple to administer, it does not meet the Condorcet criterion. Also, it is heavily affected by the entry of candidates who have no real chance of winning.
Systems that award points in a similar way but possibly with a different formula are calledpositional systems. The score vector(m − 1,m − 2, ..., 0) is associated with the Borda count,(1, 1/2, 1/3, ..., 1/m) defines theDowdall system and(1, 0, ..., 0) equates tofirst-past-the-post.
Instant-runoff voting, often conflated with ranked-choice voting in general, is a contingent ranked-vote voting method that recursively eliminates theplurality loser of an election until one candidate has the majority of the remaining votes. In the given example, candidateA is declared winner in the third round, having received a majority of votes through the accumulation of first-choice votes and redistributed votes from candidateB. This system embodies the voters' preferences between the final candidates, stopping when a candidate garners the preference of a majority of voters. Instant-runoff voting does not fulfill theCondorcet winner criterion.
Single transferable voting is a contingent ranked-vote voting method that elects multiple members. It elects any candidates who achieve quota, and if necessary recursively eliminates theplurality loser at each stage of the vote count and transfers surplus votes of winners until enough are elected by quota or by still being in the running when the field of candidates is thinned to the number of remaining open seats. Because elected members are elected with the same or about the same number of votes, each party popular enough for representation receives a number of seats appropriate to the vote tallies of its candidates. The transfers reduce waste to about one quota - which in a five-seat district is about 17 percent of valid votes; in districts with more members than five, the waste is smaller. All but one quota of votes approximately are used to actually elect someone in the district so the percentage of effective votes is dependably about 80 to 90 percent of valid votes.[29][30]
The defeat-dropping Condorcet methods all look for a Condorcet winner, i.e. a candidate who is not defeated by any other candidate in a one-on-one majority vote. If there is no Condorcet winner, they repeatedly drop (set the margin to zero) for the one-on-one matchups that are closest to being tied, until there is a Condorcet winner. How "closest to being tied" is defined depends on the specific rule. For theMinimax Condorcet method, the elections with the smallest margin of victory are dropped, whereas inranked pairs only elections that create a cycle are eligible to be dropped (with defeats being dropped based on the margin of victory).
Condorcet winner. If a candidate is the winning candidate in every paired comparison, the candidate shall be declared the winner of the election.
Ordinal utility is a measure of preferences in terms of rank orders—that is, first, second, etc. ...Cardinal utility is a measure of preferences on a scale of cardinal numbers, such as the scale from zero to one or the scale from one to ten.
The method was, however, mentioned by Condorcet, but only to be condemned.
En effet, lorsqu'il y a plus de trois concurrents, le véritable vœu de la pluralité peut être pour un candidat qui n'ait eu aucune des voix dans le premier scrutin.