Movatterモバイル変換


[0]ホーム

URL:


Jump to content
WikipediaThe Free Encyclopedia
Search

Possible world

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Concept of philosophy and logic used to express modal claims
"Possible worlds" redirects here. For other uses, seePossible Worlds.

Apossible world is a complete and consistent way the world is or could have been. Possible worlds are widely used as a formal device inlogic,philosophy, andlinguistics in order to provide a semantics forintensional andmodal logic. Theirmetaphysical status has been a subject of controversy inphilosophy, withmodal realists such asDavid Lewis arguing that they are literally existing alternate realities, and others such asRobert Stalnaker arguing that they are not.

Logic

[edit]
See also:Modal logic § Semantics, andIntensional logic

Possible worlds are one of the foundational concepts inmodal andintensional logics. Formulas in these logics are used to represent statements about whatmight be true, whatshould be true, what onebelieves to be true and so forth. To give these statements a formal interpretation, logicians use structures containing possible worlds. For instance, in therelational semantics for classical propositional modal logic, the formulaP{\displaystyle \Diamond P} (read as "possibly P") is actually true if and only ifP{\displaystyle P} is true in some world which isaccessible from the actual world.

Possible worlds play a central role in the work of both linguists and/or philosophers working informal semantics. Contemporary formal semantics is couched in formal systems rooted inMontague grammar, which is itself built onRichard Montague'sintensional logic.[1] Contemporary research in semantics typically uses possible worlds as formal tools without committing to a particular theory of their metaphysical status. The termpossible world is retained even by those who attach no metaphysical significance to them.

In the field ofdatabase theory, possible worlds are also a notion used in the setting ofuncertain databases andprobabilistic databases, which serve as asuccinct representation of a large number of possible worlds.[2]

Argument from ways

[edit]

Possible worlds are often regarded with suspicion, which is why their proponents have struggled to find arguments in their favor.[3] An often-cited argument is called theargument from ways. It defines possible worlds as "ways things could have been" and relies for its premises and inferences on assumptions fromnatural language,[4][5][6] for example:

  1. TheBlack Death could have killed 99% of the European population, rather than the estimated 25 to 60%.
  2. So there are other ways things could have been.
  3. Possible worlds are ways things could have been.
  4. So there are other possible worlds.

The central step of this argument happens at(2) where the plausible(1) is interpreted in a way that involvesquantification over "ways". Many philosophers, followingWillard Van Orman Quine,[7] hold that quantification entailsontological commitments, in this case, a commitment to the existence of possible worlds. Quine himself restricted his method to scientific theories, but others have applied it also to natural language, for example,Amie L. Thomasson in her paper entitledOntology Made Easy.[8] The strength of theargument from ways depends on these assumptions and may be challenged by casting doubt on the quantifier-method of ontology or on the reliability of natural language as a guide to ontology.

Philosophical issues and applications

[edit]

Metaphysics

[edit]
Further information:Modal logic § Metaphysical questions, andModal realism

Theontological status of possible worlds has provoked intense debate.David Lewis famously advocated for a position known asmodal realism, which holds that possible worlds are real, concrete places which exist in the exact same sense that the actual world exists. On Lewis's account, the actual world is special only in that we live there. This doctrine is calledthe indexicality of actuality since it can be understood as claiming that the term "actual" is anindexical, like "now" and "here". Lewis gave a variety of arguments for this position. He argued that just as the reality of atoms is demonstrated by their explanatory power in physics, so too are possible worlds justified by their explanatory power in philosophy. He also argued that possible worlds must be real because they are simply "ways things could have been" and nobody doubts that such things exist. Finally, he argued that they could not be reduced to more "ontologically respectable" entities such as maximally consistent sets of propositions without rendering theories of modality circular. (He referred to these theories as "ersatz modal realism" which try to get the benefits of possible worlds semantics "on the cheap".)[9][10]

Modal realism is controversial.W.V. Quine rejected it as "metaphysically extravagant".[11] Stalnaker responded to Lewis's arguments by pointing out that a way things could have been is not itself a world, but rather a property that such a world can have. Since properties can exist without them applying to any existing objects, there's no reason to conclude that other worlds like ours exist. Another of Stalnaker's arguments attacks Lewis'sindexicality theory of actuality. Stalnaker argues that even if the English word "actual" is an indexical, that doesn't mean that other worlds exist. For comparison, one can use the indexical "I" without believing that other people actually exist.[12] Some philosophers instead endorse the view of possible worlds as maximally consistent sets of propositions or descriptions, while others such asSaul Kripke treat them as purelyformal (i.e. mathematical) devices.[13]

Explicating necessity and possibility

[edit]

At least since Aristotle, philosophers have been greatly concerned with the logical statuses of propositions, e.g. necessity, contingency, and impossibility. In the twentieth century, possible worlds have been used to explicate these notions. In modal logic, a proposition is understood in terms of theworlds in which it is true andworlds in which it is false. Thus, equivalences like the following have been proposed:

  • True propositions are those that aretrue in the actual world (for example: "Archduke Franz Ferdinand was assassinated in 1914").
  • False propositions are those that arefalse in the actual world (for example: "Archduke Franz Ferdinand was assassinated in 2014").
  • Possible propositions are those that aretrue in at least one possible world (for example: "Archduke Franz Ferdinand survived the assassination attempt against him in 1914"). This includes propositions which are necessarily true, in the sense below.
  • Impossible propositions (ornecessarily false propositions) are those that aretrue in no possible world (for example: "Melissa and Toby are taller than each other at the same time").
  • Necessarily true propositions (often simply callednecessary propositions) are those that aretrue in all possible worlds (for example: "2 + 2 = 4"; "all bachelors are unmarried").[14]
  • Contingent propositions are those that aretrue in some possible worlds and false in others (for example: "Archduke Franz Ferdinand was assassinated in 1914" iscontingently true and "Archduke Franz Ferdinand survived the assassination attempt against him in 1914" iscontingently false).

Other uses

[edit]

Possible worlds play a central role in many other debates in philosophy. These include debates about theZombie Argument, andphysicalism andsupervenience in thephilosophy of mind. Many debates in thephilosophy of religion have been reawakened by the use of possible worlds.

History of the concept

[edit]

The idea of possible worlds is most commonly attributed toGottfried Leibniz, who spoke of possible worlds as ideas in the mind ofGod and used the notion to argue that our actually created world must be "thebest of all possible worlds".Arthur Schopenhauer argued that on the contrary our world must be the worst of all possible worlds, because if it were only a little worse it could not continue to exist.[15] Scholars have found implicit earlier traces of the idea of possible worlds in the works ofRené Descartes,[16] a major influence on Leibniz,Al-Ghazali (The Incoherence of the Philosophers),Averroes (The Incoherence of the Incoherence),[17]Fakhr al-Din al-Razi (Matalib al-'Aliya),[18]John Duns Scotus[17] and Antonio Rubio (Commentarii in libros Aristotelis Stagiritae de Coelo).[19]

The modern philosophical use of the notion was pioneered byDavid Lewis andSaul Kripke.

See also

[edit]

References

[edit]
  1. ^"Formal Semantics: Origins, Issues, Early Impact".Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication. This Proceeding of the Symposium for Cognition, Logic and Communication. Vol. 6. 2011.
  2. ^Suciu, Dan; Olteanu, Dan; Re, Christopher; Koch, Christoph (2022-05-31).Probabilistic Databases. Springer Nature.ISBN 978-3-031-01879-4. See section 1.2.2, "Possible Worlds Semantics"
  3. ^Lewis, David K. (1973). "4. Foundations".Counterfactuals. Blackwell.
  4. ^Laan, David A. Vander (1997)."The Ontology of Impossible Worlds".Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic.38 (4):597–620.doi:10.1305/ndjfl/1039540772.
  5. ^Berto, Francesco; Jago, Mark (2018)."Impossible Worlds".The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved14 November 2020.
  6. ^Menzel, Christopher (2017)."Possible Worlds".The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved14 November 2020.
  7. ^Quine, Willard V. (1948)."On What There Is".Review of Metaphysics.2 (1):21–38.
  8. ^Thomasson, Amie L. (2014).Ontology Made Easy. Oup Usa. p. 248.
  9. ^Lewis, David (1973).Counterfactuals. John Wiley & Sons.
  10. ^Lewis, David (1986).On the plurality of worlds. Wiley-Blackwell.
  11. ^W. V. O. Quine,"Proportional Objects" in Ontological Relativity and Other Essays', 1969, pp.140-147
  12. ^Stalnaker, Robert (1976). "Possible worlds".Noûs.10 (1):65–75.doi:10.2307/2214477.JSTOR 2214477.
  13. ^Kripke, Saul (1972).Naming and necessity. Harvard University Press.
  14. ^See "A Priori and A Posteriori" (author: Jason S. Baehr), atInternet Encyclopedia of Philosophy: "A necessary proposition is one the truth value of which remains constant across all possible worlds. Thus a necessarily true proposition is one that is true in every possible world, and a necessarily false proposition is one that is false in every possible world. By contrast, the truth value of contingent propositions is not fixed across all possible worlds: for any contingent proposition, there is at least one possible world in which it is true and at least one possible world in which it is false." Accessed 7 July 2012.
  15. ^Arthur Schopenhauer, "Die Welt als Wille und Vorstellung," supplement to the 4th book "Von der Nichtigkeit und dem Leiden des Lebens" p. 2222, see also R.B. Haldane and J. Kemp's translation"On the Vanity and Suffering of Life" pp 395-6
  16. ^"Nor could we doubt that, if God had created many worlds, they would not be as true in all of them as in this one. Thus those who could examine sufficiently the consequences of these truths and of our rules, could be able to discover effects by their causes, and, to explain myself in the language of the schools, they could have a priori demonstrations of everything that could be produced in this new world." -The World, Chapter VII
  17. ^abTaneli Kukkonen (2000), "Possible Worlds in the Tahâfut al-Falâsifa: Al-Ghazâlî on Creation and Contingency",Journal of the History of Philosophy,38 (4):479–502,doi:10.1353/hph.2005.0033,S2CID 170995877
  18. ^Adi Setia (2004),"Fakhr Al-Din Al-Razi on Physics and the Nature of the Physical World: A Preliminary Survey",Islam & Science,2, retrieved2010-03-02
  19. ^Padilla Gálvez, Jesús (1948)."The Best of all possible worlds"(PDF).Cuadernos Salmantinos de Filosofía.45 (1):231–259.

Further reading

[edit]
  • D.M. Armstrong,A World of States of Affairs (1997. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)ISBN 0-521-58948-7
  • John Divers,Possible Worlds (2002. London: Routledge)ISBN 0-415-15556-8
  • Paul Herrick,The Many Worlds of Logic (1999. Oxford: Oxford University Press) Chapters 23 and 24.ISBN 978-0-19-515503-7
  • David Lewis,On the Plurality of Worlds (1986. Oxford & New York: Basil Blackwell)ISBN 0-631-13994-X
  • Michael J. Loux [ed.]The Possible and the Actual (1979. Ithaca & London: Cornell University Press)ISBN 0-8014-9178-9
  • G.W. Leibniz,Theodicy (2001. Wipf & Stock Publishers)ISBN 978-0-87548-437-2
  • Brian Skyrms, "Possible Worlds, Physics and Metaphysics" (1976. Philosophical Studies 30)

External links

[edit]
National
Other
Major fields
Logics
Theories
Foundations
Lists
Topics
Other
Central concepts
Topics
Areas
Phenomena
Formalism
Formal systems
Concepts
See also
Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Possible_world&oldid=1241008838"
Categories:
Hidden categories:

[8]ページ先頭

©2009-2025 Movatter.jp