Part of a series on |
Bayesian statistics |
---|
![]() |
Posterior =Likelihood ×Prior ÷Evidence |
Background |
Model building |
Posterior approximation |
Estimators |
Evidence approximation |
Model evaluation |
Instatistics, thelikelihood principle is the proposition that, given astatistical model, all the evidence in asample relevant to model parameters is contained in thelikelihood function.
A likelihood function arises from aprobability density function considered as a function of its distributional parameterization argument. For example, consider a model which gives the probability density function of observablerandom variable as a function of a parameter . Then for a specific value of, the function is a likelihood function of : it gives a measure of how "likely" any particular value of is, if we know that has the value . The density function may be a density with respect to counting measure, i.e. aprobability mass function.
Two likelihood functions areequivalent if one is a scalar multiple of the other.[a]Thelikelihood principle is this: All information from the data that is relevant to inferences about the value of the model parameters is in the equivalence class to which the likelihood function belongs. Thestrong likelihood principle applies this same criterion to cases such as sequential experiments where the sample of data that is available results from applying astopping rule to the observations earlier in the experiment.[1]
Suppose
Then the observation that induces the likelihood function
while the observation that induces the likelihood function
The likelihood principle says that, as the data are the same in both cases, the inferences drawn about the value of should also be the same. In addition, all the inferential content in the data about the value of is contained in the two likelihoods, and is the same if they are proportional to one another. This is the case in the above example, reflecting the fact that the difference between observing and observing lies not in the actual data collected, nor in the conduct of the experimenter, but in the two differentdesigns of the experiment.
Specifically, in one case, the decision in advance was to try twelve times, regardless of the outcome; in the other case, the advance decision was to keep trying until three successes were observed.If you support the likelihood principle then inference about should be the same for both cases because the two likelihoods are proportional to each other: Except for a constant leading factor of220 vs.55, the two likelihood functions are the same – constant multiples of each other.
This equivalence is not always the case, however. The use offrequentist methods involvingp values leads to different inferences for the two cases above,[2]showing that the outcome of frequentist methods depends on the experimental procedure, and thus violates the likelihood principle.
A related concept is thelaw of likelihood, the notion that the extent to which the evidence supports one parameter value or hypothesis against another is indicated by the ratio of their likelihoods, theirlikelihood ratio. That is,
is the degree to which the observationx supports parameter value or hypothesisa againstb. If this ratio is 1, the evidence is indifferent; if greater than 1, the evidence supports the valuea againstb; or if less, then vice versa.
InBayesian statistics, this ratio is known as theBayes factor, andBayes' rule can be seen as the application of the law of likelihood to inference.
Infrequentist inference, the likelihood ratio is used in thelikelihood-ratio test, but other non-likelihood tests are used as well. TheNeyman–Pearson lemma states the likelihood-ratio test is equallystatistically powerful as the most powerful test for comparing twosimple hypotheses at a givensignificance level, which gives a frequentist justification for the law of likelihood.
Combining the likelihood principle with the law of likelihood yields the consequence that the parameter value which maximizes the likelihood function is the value which is most strongly supported by the evidence. This is the basis for the widely used method ofmaximum likelihood.
The likelihood principle was first identified by that name in print in 1962 (Barnardet al.,Birnbaum, and Savageet al.), but arguments for the same principle, unnamed, and the use of the principle in applications goes back to the works ofR.A. Fisher in the 1920s. The law of likelihood was identified by that name byI. Hacking (1965). More recently the likelihood principle as a general principle of inference has been championed byA.W.F. Edwards. The likelihood principle has been applied to thephilosophy of science by R. Royall.[3]
Birnbaum (1962) initially argued that the likelihood principle follows from two more primitive and seemingly reasonable principles, theconditionality principle and thesufficiency principle:
However, upon further consideration Birnbaum rejected both his conditionality principle and the likelihood principle.[4] The adequacy of Birnbaum's original argument has also been contested by others (see below for details).
Some widely used methods of conventional statistics, for example manysignificance tests, are not consistent with the likelihood principle.
Let us briefly consider some of the arguments for and against the likelihood principle.
According to Giere (1977),[5] Birnbaum rejected[4] both his own conditionality principle and the likelihood principle because they were both incompatible with what he called the “confidence concept of statistical evidence”, which Birnbaum (1970) describes as taking “from the Neyman-Pearson approach techniques for systematically appraising and bounding the probabilities (under respective hypotheses) of seriously misleading interpretations of data” ([4] p. 1033). The confidence concept incorporates only limited aspects of the likelihood concept and only some applications of the conditionality concept. Birnbaum later notes that it was the unqualified equivalence formulation of his 1962 version of the conditionality principle that led “to the monster of the likelihood axiom” ([6] p. 263).
Birnbaum's original argument for the likelihood principle has also been disputed by other statisticians includingAkaike,[7] Evans[8] and philosophers of science, includingDeborah Mayo.[9][10]Dawid points out fundamental differences between Mayo's and Birnbaum's definitions of the conditionality principle, arguing Birnbaum's argument cannot be so readily dismissed.[11] A new proof of the likelihood principle has been provided by Gandenberger that addresses some of the counterarguments to the original proof.[12]
Unrealized events play a role in some common statistical methods. For example, the result of asignificance test depends on thep-value, the probability of a result as extreme or more extreme than the observation, and that probability may depend on the design of the experiment. To the extent that the likelihood principle is accepted, such methods are therefore denied.
Some classical significance tests are not based on the likelihood. The following are a simple and more complicated example of those, using a commonly cited example calledtheoptional stopping problem.
Suppose I tell you that I tossed a coin 12 times and in the process observed 3 heads. You might make some inference about the probability of heads and whether the coin was fair.
Suppose now I tell that I tossed the coinuntil I observed 3 heads, and I tossed it 12 times. Will you now make some different inference?
The likelihood function is the same in both cases: It is proportional to
So according to thelikelihood principle, in either case the inference should be the same.
Suppose a number of scientists are assessing the probability of a certain outcome (which we shall call 'success') in experimental trials. Conventional wisdom suggests that if there is no bias towards success or failure then the success probability would be one half. Adam, a scientist, conducted 12 trials and obtains 3 successes and 9 failures.One of those successes was the 12th and last observation. Then Adam left the lab.
Bill, a colleague in the same lab, continued Adam's work and published Adam's results, along with a significance test. He tested thenull hypothesis thatp, the success probability, is equal to a half, versusp < 0.5 . If we ignore the information that the third success was the 12th and last observation, the probability of the observed result that out of 12 trials 3 or something fewer (i.e. more extreme) were successes, ifH0 is true, is
which is299/4096 = 7.3% . Thus the null hypothesis is not rejected at the 5% significance level if we ignore the knowledge that the third success was the 12th result.
However observe that this first calculation also includes 12 token long sequences that end in tails contrary to the problem statement!
If we redo this calculation we realize the likelihood according to the null hypothesis must be the probability of a fair coin landing 2 or fewer heads on 11 trials multiplied with the probability of the fair coin landing a head for the 12th trial:
which is67/20481/2 =67/4096 = 1.64% . Now the resultis statistically significant at the5% level.
Charlotte, another scientist, reads Bill's paper and writes a letter, saying that it is possible that Adam kept trying until he obtained 3 successes, in which case the probability of needing to conduct 12 or more experiments is given by
which is134/40961/2 = 1.64% . Now the resultis statistically significant at the5% level. Note that there is no contradiction between the latter two correct analyses; both computations are correct, and result in the same p-value.
To these scientists, whether a result is significant or not does not depend on the design of the experiment, but does on the likelihood (in the sense of the likelihood function) of the parameter value being 1/2 .
Results of this kind are considered by some as arguments against the likelihood principle. For others it exemplifies the value of the likelihood principle and is an argument against significance tests.
Similar themes appear when comparingFisher's exact test withPearson's chi-squared test.
An argument in favor of the likelihood principle is given by Edwards in his bookLikelihood. He cites the following story from J.W. Pratt, slightly condensed here. Note that the likelihood function depends only on what actually happened, and not on whatcould have happened.
This story can be translated to Adam's stopping rule above, as follows: Adam stopped immediately after 3 successes, because his boss Bill had instructed him to do so. After the publication of the statistical analysis by Bill, Adam realizes that he has missed a later instruction from Bill to instead conduct 12 trials, and that Bill's paper is based on this second instruction. Adam is very glad that he got his 3 successes after exactly 12 trials, and explains to his friend Charlotte that by coincidence he executed the second instruction. Later, Adam is astonished to hear about Charlotte's letter, explaining thatnow the result is significant.