Analogy inlaw is a method of resolving issues on which there is no previous authority by usingargument from analogy. Analogy in general involves an inference drawn from one particular situation to another based on similarity, but legal analogy is distinguished by the need to use a legally relevant basis for drawing an analogy between two situations. It may be applied to various forms oflegal authority, includingstatutory law andcase law.
In thecivil law andcommon law traditions, the basis of legal relevance that allows drawing a legally valid analogy is described by different terms depending on the source of law involved:ratio decidendi for precedent,ratio legis for statutory law, andratio iuris for unwritten legal principles. The use of analogy in both traditions is broadly described by the traditional maximUbi eadem est ratio, ibi idem ius (where the reason is the same, the law is the same).
Although all legal systems use analogy in some fashion, different jurisdictions and legal traditions apply or limit analogy in many different ways. The civil law and common law traditions differ most prominently in the subject matter to which analogy is typically applied: in civil law courts, analogy is most typically employed to fill in gaps in a statute, while in common law courts it is most commonly used to apply and extend precedent. In addition, these legal systems have developed elaborate typologies of analogy, although these are often disputed.
The analogical extension of criminal penalties ("punishment by analogy") and tax liability is prohibited in many modern jurisdictions, under the various legal principles that safeguard legal certainty. Historically, however, punishment by analogy has been part of many legal systems, including those ofimperial China, the earlyUSSR, and thePeople's Republic of China prior to 1998. A few countries have retained legal provisions that at least nominally allow for punishment by analogy.
Legal analogy is usually considered distinct fromextensive interpretation, which stays within the words of existing law. However, some authorities argue that the distinction between the two is unclear or untenable, as both approaches extending the effect of a statute beyond its literal words based on the purpose or intent of the legislature.[1] Some authorities do not distinguish between the two at all.[2]
The use ofinductive reasoning to derive a general rule from multiple legal norms or precedents and apply it to a new case is sometimes regarded as a form of analogy, for example [[#Analogia iuris|analogia iuris]], but is sometimes considered a distinct form of legal argument since it does not involve a direct analogy from an established case to a new one.
Legal analogy is also distinguished from related forms of legal argument that also turn on the underlying reason for a legal norm, such asargumentum e contrario andargumentum a fortiori.
The analogical interpretation of statutes may also be distinguished from interpretation by implication, although this distinction is not commonly drawn in the civil law tradition.[3]
In broad terms, the use of analogy in law arises from the presumption that similar principles should apply to similar cases. In this broad sense, some legal scholars have argued that all legal reasoning is analogical.
More particularly, the general method of legal analogy has been described as having four steps:[5]
The question of what makes the analogized case relevant generally turns on the reason for the existing norm (for example, theratio legis of a statute or theratio decidendi of a judicial precedent).[6]
The detailed application of this method varies by thesource of law. Within a legal system, the permitted use of analogy may vary greatly for example between statutory law and case law.
Incase law, which is most prominently associated with the common law legal tradition, analogies are drawn fromprecedential cases. In the strongest case, a judge who decides a case at hand may find that the facts of the case are so similar to the facts of a prior case that the outcomes of these cases should be the same:stare decisis. Reasoning from the absence of analogy is also done, when a judgedistinguishes a precedent and declines to apply it to the case at hand.
In one formulation, the method of analogy in applying precedent has the following steps:[7]
An often-cited example of analogical reasoning in case law isAdams v. New Jersey Steamboat Co., in which theNew York Court of Appeals was called upon to decide whether a steamboat line was liable for money being stolen from a passenger's stateroom, even if neither the passenger nor the crew had been negligent.[8] There was no settled rule of precedent for steamboat liability. If the same event had occurred at an inn, the innkeeper would have been liable. In deciding the case, judgeDenis O'Brien wrote that a steamboat passenger "procures and pays for his room for the same reasons that a guest at an inn does" and that a "steamer carrying passengers upon the water, and furnishing them with rooms and entertainment, is, for all practical purposes, a floating inn".[4] He therefore concluded that "the duties which the proprietors owe to the passengers in their charge ought to be the same" and that "no good reason is apparent" for departing from thestrict liability that applied to innkeepers.[4] Therefore, because the cases were analogous in relevant respects and there were no countervailing considerations, the steamboat company was also liable.[4][9]
In a more recent example, inPopov v. Hayashi, a valuable baseball was caught by two different people, confronting theCalifornia Superior Court with a fact pattern not governed by established legal standards forpossession.[10] The court reasoned by analogy with a New Jersey case involving children tossing an abandoned sock that turned out to contain money in determining that possession required both physical control and intent, and that under the circumstances it was appropriate to order anequitable division among the two people who caught the baseball.[11] The court's decision inPopov has been analogized to the civil law practice ofanalogia legis to fill in gaps in existing legal norms.[11]
Instatutory interpretation, analogy is used chiefly in civil law legal systems to extend a statute to cover new situations that are outside the actual language of the statute but within its underlying justification. This kind of statutory interpretation by analogy is formally recognized in the civil codes of most civil law jurisdictions, in bothanalogia legis andanalogia iuris forms.[12] In practice, however, such analogies come into play in only a small minority of cases. A 1978 survey of approximately 1,000 German civil cases found that only 1/20 of them involved statutory analogies.[13]
In addition, a form of analogy also used by the courts in common law jurisdictions to interpret statutes is analogous interpretation: if there are two similar statutes and one has already been construed, the court may construe the second statute by analogy to the construction of the first. This has been referred to as "analogical extensive interpretation".[14]
Some statutes expressly provide for their provisions to be applied analogously. This statutory mandate to analogize gives the resulting analogies greater legal weight.[15] One form of statutorily-mandated analogy ismutatis mutandis application, often translated as "analogous application". For example, theDutch euthanasia statute provides for the provisions regarding an informed decision by the patient to be appliedmutatis mutandis where the patient is incapable of making such decisions.[16]
A more unusual example of mandated analogy is found in theDutch civil code of 1992, where certain provisions governing liability for animals and dangerous objects call on the judge to analogize the case to a counterfactual. For example, Article 6:179 provides that the possessor of an animal is liable for damage unless the possessor would not have been liable, even if the animal was under his control, under the limitations of liability in the preceding section.[17]
Even in jurisdictions that do not widely practice statutory analogy, analogical methods may be used for interpretingconstitutional law. For example, in Canada, theSection 15 Charter right to be free of discrimination covers not only the specific grounds for discrimination listed in the Charter, but also "analogous" grounds such as sexual orientation and marital status.[18] The analogous prohibition inSection 9 of the Constitution of South Africa has also been similarly extended to protect against forms of discrimination analogous to those listed in the constitution.[18]
In United States constitutional law, rights implied by analogy are often referred to as being in thepenumbra of theBill of Rights. This terminology was used byOliver Wendell Holmes Jr. to describe rights developed by analogy to the Fourth and Fifth Amendments of the US Constitution, and also later byWilliam O. Douglas to describe rights implied by various constitutional amendments, which he regarded as protected by theNinth Amendment.[19]
In 2022, inNYSRPA v. Bruen, the United States Supreme Court adopted a doctrine that requires courts to use historical analogies to determine whether a statute violates theSecond Amendment to the United States Constitution.[20]
The theory of penumbral rights developed by analogy with those articulated in the constitution has also been adopted in other countries. For example, courts in Bangladesh and India have used penumbral theory to extend a constitutional guarantee of the right to life to a right to a healthy environment.[21]
Teleological interpretation is commonly practiced by international tribunals.[22] It is particularly associated with the jurisprudence of theEuropean Court of Justice in interpreting theTreaties of the European Union. A teleological approach entails the frequent use of analogy to ensure that the purpose of a treaty's drafters is adequately served.
In addition, some treaties expressly call for their provisions to be interpreted analogously in certain situations. For example, theFirst Geneva Convention directly addresses the actions of belligerents, but in Article 6 also calls for neutral powers to apply its provisions by analogy.[23]
Various classifications of legal analogy have been proposed. One typology that has been influential in the civil law tradition classifies legal analogies asintra legem orextra legem based on thelegal gaps that they fill:
Other terms are also used:
Analogia legis, also known as "statutory analogy" or "analogy from statute", is a method ofstatutory interpretation in which the legal principle applicable to afact pattern not covered by alegal norm is determined by analogy to a norm that governs a comparable situation.
The analogy is typically governed by theratio legis, or underlying purpose of the statute.[26] For example, in a 2010 decision, theItalian Constitutional Court determined that a statute allowing drivers of public transport vehicles to carry only an authenticated photocopy of thevehicle registration, rather than the originals, also extended to waste haulers, even though they were not expressly covered by the statute, because the same legislative purpose applied in both cases.[27]
Whenanalogia legis is not possible thenanalogia iuris may apply, in which the analogy is derived not from a statute but from fundamental legal or constitutional principles.Analogia iuris has also been described as the court constructing a new, previously unarticulated general principle of law.[28][29] However, although the distinction betweenanalogia legis andanalogia juris is traditional, some authorities have argued that there is no tenable distinction between them, as both involve the same interpretive techniques.[29]
A prominent example ofanalogia iuris occurred in the Dutch case ofQuint v. Te Poel, decided by theDutch Supreme Court in 1959, in which homebuilders sought compensation from the owner of the property on which they had built homes, although the owner was not a party to the homebuilders' contract. TheDutch Civil Code of 1838, which was then in effect, contained clauses prohibiting specific examples ofunjust enrichment but did not contain any general prohibition on unjust enrichment. The court generalized from these existing provisions to create a new cause of action for unjust enrichment, allowing the builders to recover from the property owner.[30]
Analogia legis is formally recognized in thecivil codes of many jurisdictions. ThePortuguese Civil Code for example provides that "cases for which the law does not provide shall be governed by the norm applicable to similar cases".[31] Some countries, such asUkraine, formally recognize bothanalogia legis andanalogia iuris by name in their civil codes. A number of European countries, including Italy and Slovenia,[32] follow the example of theAustrian civil code in that they provide for bothanalogia legis andanalogia juris, but describe them rather than naming them:
If a case cannot be decided based on either the words of a statute or the natural sense of the statute, consideration must be given to similar cases that have been decided in the statutes and the bases of other statutes related to it. If the case remains in doubt, the case must be decided according to natural principles of law, with regard to the carefully collected and maturely considered facts.[33]
Ronald Dworkin's distinction between legal rules andlegal principles has sometimes been adopted to distinguish rule-based analogies, which seek to fill in gaps in a system of rules, and principle-based analogies, which analogize specific cases based on deeper values of the legal system.[34]Bartosz Brożek has argued that rule-based analogies, as well as "factual analogies" which purport to be based purely on factual similarity, are only justifiable if they rest on principles.[35]
The principles of legal analogy vary among jurisdictions. Sometimes the use of analogy is forbidden: the most common such limitation is on theuse of analogy to extend criminal liability.
Some authorities argue against the use of analogy in legal reasoning entirely, for example on the basis that it is essentiallyad hoc or unscientific. In the American tradition, for example,Frederick Schauer argued that analogy in caselaw can only involve deduction from a rule that happens to apply to both cases.[36]Richard Posner regards analogy as merely a mixture of induction, deduction, and rhetoric, which would be better replaced by straightforward considerations of correctness and stability.[36]Lawrence A. Alexander criticized analogy for entrenching the errors made in past cases.[37] In Alexander's phrasing, analogical reasoning in law amounts to asking the question "what would be morally correct in a world in which moral errors were not errors?"[38] Less forcefully, some authorities argue that analogy is at best aheuristic tool, without any argumentative force of its own.[39]
For those authorities that recognize a proper role for analogy in law, some common limitations include the following:
In most legal systems today, analogy cannot be used in the interpretation of criminal statutes, unless the result is favorable to the accused.[45] Such a ban finds its footing in the maximnullum crimen, nulla poena sine lege (no crime or punishment without law), which is understood in the way that there is no crime or punishment unless it is plainly provided for in a law-controlled provision or an already existing judicial precedent. Some jurisdictions such as Germany also extend this prohibition to lesser punishments such ascontraventions, and to disciplinary proceedings against public servants, even if these are not considered criminal in nature.[46]
In its modern, absolute form, this prohibition is of relatively recent origin. Early modern common law commentators such as Edmund Plowden encouraged the analogical construction of both civil and criminal statutes.[47] In English law, the modern prohibition took hold in the 18th century and was adopted by commentators such asBlackstone andMatthew Bacon.[48]
Among civil law jurisdictions, punishment by analogy was expressly provided for under several early criminal codes, including the Prussian code of 1721 and theConstitutio Criminalis Theresiana of 1769.[49] This practice was criticized by Enlightenment theorists such as Montesquieu and Beccaria.[49]
The first criminal code to bar the use of analogy was the Austrian penal code of 1787.[50] Such bans quickly spread across Europe in the late 18th and 19th centuries, reaching Prussia in 1794 and Germany in 1871.[50] However, punishment by analogy continued to be allowed under theRussian penal code of 1845,[51] and also in Nazi German law following the decree of June 28, 1935.[52]
Forms of legal analogy arose in antiquity in several traditions, including classical Greek, Indian, and Chinese law. The exact uses and doctrines surrounding legal analogy have developed differently in various different legal traditions.
In the law courts of ancient Athens, where decisions were made by the jury ofdikastai, arguments by analogy were commonly used.[53] For example, the fourth-century BCE oratorIsaeus argued against the validity of a will made by a minor by reference to a law prohibiting minors from making contracts.[54]
In theNicomachean Ethics, Aristotle advanced an "equitable" theory of statutory interpretation that became the basis of many Western approaches to analogical interpretation:
When therefore the law lays down a general rule, and thereafter a case arises which is an exception to the rule, it is then right, where the lawgiver's pronouncement because of its absoluteness is defective and erroneous, to rectify the defect by deciding as the lawgiver would himself decide if he were present on the occasion, and would have enacted if he had been cognizant of the case in question.[55]
Aristotle's teaching has been adopted historically by authorities in both civil law and common law.[56]
In Roman legal oratory, arguing for a statutory interpretation by analogy was one of several techniques for arguing against a literal interpretation. In that context it was calledexemplo multarum legum, "by example of many laws".[57] This technique was widely used by orators but was not recognized by jurists such asSalvius Julianus. Instead, the jurists largely restricted their use of analogy to drawing analogies among similar juristic precedents.[58]
In theBrehon law tradition of Ireland, which first entered the written record in early medieval times, analogy (cosmailius) was one of the sources of law on which a judge could base a decision.[59] Analogy was often used to adapt traditional legal maxims to new technologies. For example, various precepts governingwater mills were developed by analogy after that technology was introduced in the third century.[60]
A Brehon law text that employed analogy particularly extensively was theBechbretha, or "Bee-Judgments", tentatively dated to the 7th century. The author set forth legal principles governingbeekeeping based on analogies to existing legal principles governing cattle and fruit trees. For example, theBechbretha provides that if a beehive was established in a tree overhanging a neighbor's land, the swarms from that hive would become the neighbor's property in every fourth year.[61]
A famous although possibly apocryphal example of analogy in Brehon law was kingDiarmait mac Cerbaill's sixth-century ruling on a dispute betweenColumba andFinnian of Movilla over the copying of a religious text, which has been described as the world's firstcopyright case. According to a possibly apocryphal account first recorded in the 16th century, the king resolved the dispute by analogy to the legal maxim "to every cow her calf", declaring likewise "to every book its copy", so that Columba's copy of the book remained Finnian's property.[62] This has been described as the oldest recordedcopyright infringement case.[63]
Inthe civil law tradition, the systematic use of analogy dates to medieval times, when theglossators and subsequent commentators used it to fill in gaps in the topics covered by the Roman legal authorities such as theCodex of Justinian.[64] The fourteenth-century juristLucas de Penna wrote that "where the reason is the same or greater, the law is drawn to a similar case even if not expressed".[65] A long tradition supports the use of analogical reasoning, including bothanalogia legis andanalogia iuris (analogy of statute and analogy of justice), to extend statutes to cover new situations or to articulate previously implicit legal principles.
Analogy in general is often described by one or another form of a medieval Latin maxim,Ubi eadem ratio, ibi idem ius (where the reason is the same, the law is the same). This maxim was formulated by the glossatorAzo of Bologna in the thirteenth century.[66] It was used to justify extending a limited prohibition on criminal appeals for a few heinous crimes to cover all crimes, on the theory that the same reason applied in all cases.[67] It has subsequently become a commonplace of both civil and common law.
The modern systematic distinction betweenanalogia legis andanalogia iuris was first articulated in 1797 by the German juristCarl Ludwig Wilhelm von Grolmann.[68] Grolmann did not use the Latin terms, but referred to these two forms of analogy respectively asRechtsanalogie andGesetzesanalogie.[69] A more thorough justification of the distinction between these two forms of analogy was subsequently articulated byCarl Georg von Wächter.[70]
In modern civil law, the most typical use of analogy is to fillgaps in existing statutory law. A judge wishing to apply analogical techniques must first show that there is a gap in existing law (which the legislature did not intend to leave unfilled) and that there are no constitutional barriers to the use of analogy.[71]
In common law systems, analogy has traditionally been considered a cornerstone of legal argument and judicial decisionmaking.[72] The most typical use of analogy in common law is to extend aprecedent from one case to a legally similar one.[73] However, some modern authorities such asRichard Posner have challenged whether analogy is a valid method of judicial reasoning at all.[74]
The use of analogy instatutory interpretation has a long and controversial history in the common law. In early English law, judicial extensions of statutory language were commonplace.[75] After the mid-14th century, however, this came to be recognized as outside the judicial role.[75] English courts continued, however, to extend statutes by analogy to the extent that cases involved the "same mischief" with which the statute was concerned.[76] By the sixteenth century this practice was justified under the Aristotelian doctrine of "equity of the statute" (lequity de lestatut).[76] In an influential sixteenth-century formulation,Edmund Plowden analogized the relationship of the statute and its equitable interpretation to the relationship between a seed and the fruit around it.[77] Plowden described the use of analogy in statutory interpretation as the power of a court to extend the scope of a statute so that "when the words of a statute enact one thing, they enact all other things which are in the like degree."[78]
The equity of the statute doctrine largely fell out of favor in the late 18th century, coming to be regarded as a breach of theseparation of powers or ofparliamentary sovereignty. Instead, using analogical reasoning to extend statutes to new situations came to be prohibited under the maxim thatcasus omissus pro omisso habendus est (an omitted case is to be taken as intentionally omitted). This principle is often referred to as the "casus omissus rule" or in contemporary United Statestextualist scholarship the "omitted-case canon".[40] Analogical interpretations continued to be made, for example in the early United Status admiralty case ofTalbot v. Seeman, although this may have been due to the perception of admiralty law as a unique field governed by custom rather than statute.[79][80]
In most common law jurisdictions today, analogy is largely reserved for the interpretation ofprecedent.[81] Analogizing a precedent to new facts is approximately the reverse ofdistinguishing a precedent, although the two are not exactly symmetrical.[81]
In Islamic law, the practice ofqiyas (قياس) embraces analogy as well as other related forms of interpretation. Qiyas includes for exampleargumentum a fortiori andreductio ad absurdum.[82]
A classic example of analogical reasoning under qiyas is the extension of the Quranic prohibition on wine to cover all alcoholic beverages. The qiyas method was originally developed by the early Islamic juristAbu Hanifa and is given particular prominence in theHanafi school.
Qiyas is rejected by theZahiri school, and was famously criticized by the Andalusian scholarIbn Hazm.[83] TheShia tradition also largely rejects qiyas. For example,al-Shaykh al-Mufid criticized the use of analogy to prohibit all intoxicating beverages, because some beverages could also have other properties that are more important to God.[84] However, both Zahiri and Shia scholars have adopted more limited forms of analogical reasoning.[85]
Attitudes toward analogy in socialist criminal law have varied. Acceptance of punishment by analogy has often been associated withlegal nihilism.[86]
Punishment by analogy was permitted under the Basic Principles of the Criminal Law of the USSR adopted in 1924 and the subsequentRSFSR Penal Code of 1926, which served as a model for the criminal codes of many Soviet republics.[87] In practice punishment by analogy was rare and largely limited topolitical crimes.[88] Stalin's 1936 call for legal stabilization reduced the use of analogy in Soviet criminal law, but the practice continued thanks to the advocacy of the legal theoristAndrey Vyshinsky, who championed the limited use of analogy.[89] Legal reforms adopted in 1958, after Vyshinsky's death, eliminated the provision for punishment by analogy.[90]
Punishment by analogy was also formerly permitted under the criminal law of thePeople's Republic of China; the practice was widespread under the largely uncodified criminal law of the early PRC. A 1934 statute of theChinese Soviet Republic provided that counterrevolutionary crimes not covered by the statute "shall be punished according to the article in the Statute dealing with similar crimes".[91] Efforts to reform Chinese criminal law along Soviet lines, including limiting or abolishing the use of analogy, failed in 1957 with the beginning of theAnti-Rightist Campaign.[92] The failure of this reform effort marked a major split between the Soviet and Chinese approaches to criminal law.[92] Punishment by analogy was codified in the 1980 PRC Criminal Law but was abolished in 1998.[93]
Although most Eastern European countries adopted a version of Soviet criminal law followingWorld War II, some never adopted punishment by analogy; these included Czechoslovakia, East Germany, Hungary, and Poland.[94]
Among other countries in the socialist tradition, North Korea adopted punishment by analogy in 1950 but abolished it in the criminal code reform of 2004.[95] Vietnam originally provided for punishment by analogy but abolished it in 1985.[94]
In classical Hindu law, the doctrine of atidesha (अतिदेश,atideśa), sometimes translated as "transference", developed in chapters 7 and 8 of thePurva Mimamsa Sutras was used to extend rules by analogy. Although composed byJaimini in approximately the third century BCE, the Mimamsa sutras drew on older authorities and reflected a tradition dating to around the eighth century BCE. As formulated by Jaimini, atidesha was limited to drawing analogies from a model sacrifice (prakriti) to a partially similar sacrifice (Sanskrit:vikriti).[96]
Even after the imposition of British justice, atidesha continued to be applied in British colonial courts, often relying on English translations of the relevant texts, for lawsuits between Hindus.[97] For example, in the 1872 case ofTagore v. Tagore, the court applied atidesha to analogize the prohibition on gifts to an unborn person under Hindu law to also prohibit bequests to an unborn person.[98][99] The use of atidesha continued until the 1956 codification of Hindu law.[100]
Some Indian courts have more recently claimed to apply atidesha and other Mimamsa interpretive principles in circumstances outside of Hindu religious law. JusticeB. N. Srikrishna criticized this practice and questioned whether these courts had properly applied Mimamsa principles.[101]
In traditional Chinese law, in contrast to most modern legal systems, magistrates were permitted to use analogy to extend criminal punishments to new situations. The use of analogy reflected a preference underConfucianism to avoid spelling out prohibitions in detail because doing so would encourage the public to merely do the bare minimum rather than aspiring to moral virtue.[102] As Confucius put it:[103]
If the people be led by laws, and uniformity sought to be given them by punishments, they will try to avoid the punishment, but have no sense of shame. If they be led by virtue, and uniformity sought to be given them by the rules of propriety, they will have the sense of shame, and moreover will become good.
In theTang dynasty, punishment by analogy was codified in article 50 of theTang Code, which permitted the magistrate to either analogize from a heavier penalty to show why a lighter one was appropriate in a particular case, or to analogize from a lighter penalty to show why a heavier one was appropriate.[104] TheGreat Ming Code (1397-1644) imposed strict limits on the use oflegal analogy. An official seeking to apply a provision of the Code to a situation not expressly covered in the Code or theGreat Ming Commandment was required to send the proposed punishment to theMinistry of Justice for review followed by imperial approval.[105] The use of analogy continued under theGreat Qing Legal Code, which remained in effect until 1911.[106] In one famous case, when aQing literatus improperly used a word reserved for action by the emperor to refer to an action taken by his father, he was punished by analogy under a law prohibiting commoners from manufacturing silks bearing imperial symbols.[107]
Ubi enim eadem vel major est ratio, trahitur lex ad casum simile etiam non expressum.