Human nature comprises the fundamentaldispositions and characteristics—including ways ofthinking,feeling, andacting—thathumans are said to havenaturally. The term is often used to denote theessence ofhumankind, or what it 'means' to be human. This usage has proven to be controversial in that there is dispute as to whether or not such an essence actually exists.
Arguments about human nature have been a central focus ofphilosophy for centuries and the concept continues to provoke lively philosophical debate.[1][2][3] While both concepts are distinct from one another, discussions regarding human nature are typically related to those regarding the comparative importance ofgenes andenvironment inhuman development (i.e., 'nature versus nurture'). Accordingly, the concept also continues to play a role in academic fields, such as both thenatural and thesocial sciences, andphilosophy, in which various theorists claim to have yielded insight into human nature.[4][5][6][7] Human nature is traditionally contrasted with human attributes that vary amongsocieties, such as those associated with specificcultures.
The concept of nature as a standard by which to make judgments is traditionally said to have begun inGreek philosophy, at least in regard to its heavy influence onWestern andMiddle Eastern languages and perspectives.[8] Bylate antiquity andmedieval times, the particular approach that came to be dominant was that ofAristotle'steleology, whereby human nature was believed to exist somehow independently of individuals, causing humans to simply become what they become. This, in turn, has been understood as also demonstrating a special connection between human nature anddivinity, whereby human nature is understood in terms offinal andformalcauses. More specifically, this perspective believes that nature itself (or a nature-creating divinity) has intentions and goals, including the goal for humanity to live naturally. Such understandings of human nature see this nature as an "idea", or "form" of a human.[9] However, the existence of this invariable andmetaphysical human nature is subject of much historical debate, continuing into modern times.
Against Aristotle's notion of a fixed human nature, the relative malleability of man has been argued especially strongly in recent centuries—firstly by earlymodernists such asThomas Hobbes,John Locke andJean-Jacques Rousseau. In hisEmile, or On Education, Rousseau wrote: "We do not know what our nature permits us to be."[10] Since the early 19th century, such thinkers asDarwin,Freud,Marx,Kierkegaard,Nietzsche, andSartre, as well asstructuralists andpostmodernists more generally, have also sometimes argued against a fixed orinnate human nature.
Charles Darwin'stheory of evolution has particularly changed the shape of the discussion, supporting the proposition that the ancestors of modern humans were not like humans today. As in much of modern science, such theories seek to explain with little or no recourse to metaphysical causation.[11] They can be offered to explain the origins of human nature and its underlying mechanisms, or to demonstrate capacities for change and diversity which would arguably[12] violate the concept of a fixed human nature.
Philosophy inclassical Greece is the ultimate origin of theWestern conception of the nature of things.[8]
According toAristotle, the philosophical study of human nature itself originated withSocrates, who turned philosophy from study of theheavens to study of the human things.[13] Though leaving no written works, Socrates is said to have studied the question of how a person should best live. It is clear from the works of his students,Plato andXenophon, and also from the accounts of Aristotle (Plato's student), that Socrates was arationalist and believed that the best life and the life most suited to human nature involvedreasoning. TheSocratic school was the dominant surviving influence in philosophical discussion in theMiddle Ages, amongstIslamic,Christian, andJewish philosophers.
Thehuman soul in the works of Plato and Aristotle has a nature that is divided in a specifically human way. One part is specifically human and rational, being further divided into (1) a part which is rational on its own; and (2) a spirited part which can understand reason. Other parts of the soul are home to desires or passions similar to those found in animals. In both Aristotle and Plato's ideas, spiritedness (thumos) is distinguished from the other passions (epithūmíā).[14] The proper function of the "rational" was to rule the other parts of the soul, helped by spiritedness. By this account, using one's reason is the best way to live, and philosophers are the highest types of humans.
Aristotle—Plato's most famous student—made some of the most famous and influential statements about human nature. In his works, apart from using a similar scheme of a divided human soul, some clear statements about human nature are made:
For Aristotle, reason is not only what is most special about humanity compared to other animals, but it is also what we were meant to achieve at our best. Much of Aristotle's description of human nature is still influential today. However, the particular teleological idea that humans are "meant" or intended to be something has become much less popular inmodern times.[19]
For the Socratics, human nature, and all natures, aremetaphysical concepts. Aristotle developed the standard presentation of this approach with histheory offour causes, whereby every living thing exhibits four aspects, or "causes:"
For example, anoak tree is made of plant cells (matter); grows from an acorn (effect); exhibits the nature of oak trees (form); and grows into a fully mature oak tree (end). According to Aristotle, human nature is an example of a formal cause. Likewise, our 'end' is to become afully actualized human being (including fully actualizing the mind). Aristotle suggests that thehuman intellect (νοῦς,noûs), while "smallest in bulk", is the most significant part of thehuman psyche and should be cultivated above all else.[20] The cultivation of learning and intellectual growth of the philosopher is thereby also the happiest and least painful life.
Human nature is a central question inChinese philosophy.[21] From theSong dynasty, the theory of innate goodness of human beings became dominant inConfucianism.[22] It is in contrast to the theory of innate evil advocated byXunzi.[23]
Mencius argues that human nature is good.[24][21][25] He understands human nature as the innate tendency to an ideal state that's expected to be formed under the right conditions.[26] Therefore, humans have the capacity to be good, even though they are not all good.[26]
According to Mencian theory, human nature contains four beginnings (端;duan) ofmorality.[27] It consists of a sense ofcompassion that develops intobenevolence (仁;ren), a sense ofshame anddisdain that develops intorighteousness (義;yi), a sense ofrespect andcourtesy that develops intopropriety (禮;li), and a sense ofright andwrong that develops intowisdom (智;zhi).[25][27] The beginnings of morality are characterized by bothaffective motivations andintuitive judgments, such as what's right and wrong,deferential, respectful, or disdainful.[27]
In Mencius' view, goodness is the result of the development of innate tendencies toward the virtues of benevolence, righteousness, wisdom, and propriety.[25] The tendencies are manifested inmoral emotions for every human being.[25] Reflection (思;si) upon the manifestations of the four beginnings leads to the development of virtues.[25] It brings recognition that virtue takes precedence over satisfaction, but a lack of reflection inhibits moral development.[27] In other words, humans have a constitution comprisingemotional predispositions that direct them to goodness.[25]
Mencius also addresses the question why the capacity for evil is not grounded in human nature.[25] If an individual becomes bad, it is not the result of his or her constitution, as their constitution contains the emotional predispositions that direct to goodness, but a matter of injuring or not fully developing his or her constitution in the appropriate direction.[25] He recognizes desires of the senses as natural predispositions distinct from the four beginnings.[27] People can be misled and led astray by their desires if they do not engage their ethical motivations.[25] He therefore places responsibility on people to reflect on the manifestations of the four beginnings.[27] Herein, it is not the function of ears and eyes but the function of the heart to reflect, as sensory organs are associated with sensual desires but the heart is the seat of feeling and thinking.[28] Mencius considers core virtues—benevolence, righteousness, propriety, and wisdom—as internal qualities that humans originally possess, so people can not attain full satisfaction by solely pursuits of self-interest due to their innate morality.[29] Wong (2018) underscores that Mencius' characterization of human nature as good means that "it contains predispositions to feel and act in morally appropriate ways and to make intuitive normative judgments that can with the right nurturing conditions give human beings guidance as to the proper emphasis to be given to the desires of the senses."[27]
Xunzi understands human nature as the basic faculties, capacities, and desires that people have from birth.[26] He views it as the animalistic instincts exhibited by humans before education, which includes greed, idleness, and desires.[30] He suggests that people can not get rid of these instincts, so the existence of this human nature necessitates education and cultivation of goodness.[30]
Xunzi argues that human nature is evil and that any goodness is the result of human activity.[21][31] It is human nature to seek profit, because humans desire for sensory satisfaction.[31] He states that "Now the nature of man is evil. It must depend on teachers and laws to become correct and achieve propriety and righteousness and then it becomes disciplined."[21] He underscores that goodness comes from the traits and habits acquired through conscious actions, which he calls artifice (偽;wei).[32][26] Therefore, morality is seen as a human artifice but not as a part of human nature.[33] His claim that human nature is bad, according toIvanhoe (1994), means that humans do not have a conception of morality and therefore must acquire it through learning, lest destructive and alienating competition inevitably arises from human desire.[34]
Legalism is based on a distrust of human nature.[30] Adherents to this philosophy do not concern themselves with whether human goodness or badness is inborn, and whether human beings possess the fundamental qualities associated with that nature.[35]
Legalists see the overwhelming majority of human beings as selfish in nature.[35][36] They hold the view that human nature is evil.[36] They believe that one should not expect that people will behave morally.[35] For instance, due to the corrupt nature of humans, they did not trust that officials would carry out their duties in a fair and impartial manner.[37] There is a perpetual political struggle, characterized by conflict among contending human actors and interests, where individuals are easily tempted due to their selfish nature at the expense of others.[36]
According to Legalism, the selfishness in human nature can not be eliminated or altered by education or self-cultivation.[35][38] It dismisses the possibility that people can overcome their selfishness and considers the possibility that people can be driven by moral commitment to be exceptionally rare.[35] Legalists do not see the individual morality of both the rulers or the ruled as an important concern in a political system.[35] Instead, Legalist thinkers such asHan Fei emphasize clear and impersonal norms and standards (such as laws, regulations, and rules) as the basis to maintain order.[35]
In Han Fei's view, a core feature of human nature is that humans are selfish, but that their desires are satiable.[38] He argues that competition for external goods produces disorder during times ofscarcity due to this nature.[38] If there is no scarcity, humans may treat each other well, but they will not become nice; it is that they do not turn to disorder when scarcity is absent.[38] Han Fei also argues that people are all motivated by their unchanging selfish core to want whatever advantage they can gain from whomever they can gain such advantage, which especially comes to expression in situations where people can act withimpunity.[38]
Legalists posit that the selfishness in human nature can be an asset rather than a threat to a state.[35] It is axiomatic in Legalism that the government can not be staffed by upright and trustworthy men of service, because every member of the elite—like any other member of society—will pursue their own interests and thus must be employed for their interests.[35] Herein, individuals must be allowed to pursue their selfish interests exclusively in a manner that benefits rather than contradicts the needs of a state.[35] Therefore, apolitical system that presupposes this human selfishness is the only viable system.[35] In contrast, a political system based on trust and respect (rather than impersonal norms and standards) brings great concern with regard to an ongoing and irresolvablepower struggle.[35]
Legalists propose that control is a foundation of governing, which is achieved through reward and punishment.[30] They view the usage of reward and punishment as effective political controls, as it is in human nature to have likes and dislikes.[36] For instance, according to the Legalist statesmanShang Yang, it is crucial to investigate the disposition of people in terms of rewards and penalties when a law is established.[35] He explains that a populace can not be driven to pursuits of agriculture or warfare if people consider these to be bitter or dangerous on the basis of calculations about their possible benefits, but people can be directed toward these pursuits through the application of positive and negative incentives.[35] On the selfishness in human nature, Han Fei remarks that "Those who act as ministers fear the penalties and hope to profit by the rewards."[38]
In Han Fei's view, the only realistic option is a political system that produces equivalents ofjunzi (君子, who are virtuous exemplars in Confucianism) but not actualjunzi.[38] This does not mean, however, that Han Fei makes a distinction betweenseeming andbeing good, as he does not entertain the idea that humans are good.[38] Rather, as human nature is constituted by self-interest, he argues that humans can be shaped behaviorally to yield social order if it is in the individual's own self-interest to abide by the norms (i.e., different interests are aligned to each other and thesocial good), which is most efficiently ensured if the norms are publicly and impartially enforced.[38]
Medieval conceptions of man were particularly stimulated by two sources, viz. theBible and the Classical philosophical tradition. In Scripture, two passages especially provided the foundation of a dynamic anthropology:Gen 1, 26 andWis 2, 23 where it is said that man was created in the “image of God”. Notheologian could dispense with a reflection on the foundations and consequences of the vision of man implied in this statement. WhileBernard of Clairvaux considered that man was the image of God by inamissiblefree will (De gratia et libero arbitrio, IV, 9; IX, 28), the majority of authors envisaged a likeness between God and man that was based on reason. Thus, according toThomas Aquinas, man can be calledimago Dei by reason of his intellectual Nature, for “intellectual nature imitates God especially in that God knows himself and loves himself” (Summa theologiae I a, q. 93, a. 4). According toBonaventure, all created being is a vestige of God, while beings endowed with intelligence are images of God since God is present in acts ofmemory,intellect andwill as their principle. By an original fusion ofChristology and the doctrine of man as image of God,Meister Eckhart wished to go beyond the traditional distinction between the Son, image of the Father, and man created in the image of God. The motif of man as amicrocosm in which the universe is reflected is of ancient origin. This understanding of the human being enjoyed immense success in the12th century when authors as different asBernardus Silvestris andGodfrey of Saint Victor made use of it.Hildegard of Bingen andHonorius Augustodunensis developed a whole system of correspondences between “the little world” and the universe, the macrocosm, correspondences that also played a far from negligible role inmedieval medicine and the doctrine of thefour temperaments. The origin of the definition of man as a “rational animal” also went back to Antiquity. The problem of the relation between theSoul and the body which was implicitly contained in this definition, gave rise to very important debates after the arrival ofAristotle in the West and the Translation ofGreek andArabic philosophical texts. Thedualist position whose cause was brilliantly defended by Bonaventure stated that man was composed of two substances, the soul being joined to the body “as mover”. It is patent that the postulate of ontological autonomy of the soul, supposed in this position, accords easily with the religious belief in theimmortality of the soul. The Aristotelian doctrine of the soul as “act of the organic body” and hence as theform of the body seemed to pose more of a problem as a thesis on which to base immortality. In accepting Aristotelianhylomorphism, Thomas Aquinas insisted on the unity of the human composite. The intellective soul is hence the form by which “man is a being in act, a body, a living thing, an animal and a man” (Summa theologiae I a, q. 76, a. 6, ad 1). By the act of intellection, which, in its exercise, is independent of the body, Thomas tried to demonstrate that the soul is capable of existing without the body: “Hence the intellectual principle, in other words the spirit, the intellect, possesses by itself an activity in which the body has no part. Now nothing can act by itself that does not exist by itself. … It remains that the human soul, i.e. the intellect, the spirit, is an incorporeal and subsistent reality” (Summa theologiae I a, q. 75, a. 2). By the 14th century (William of Ockham,Jean Buridan), the philosophical proofs of the soul's immortality were contested, but the debate was particularly lively in the 15th and early 16th centuries.Marsilio Ficino’sPlatonic Theology (1474) can be understood as a vast defence of the immortality of the soul, whilePietro Pomponazzi († 1525) fought most vigorously against the very idea of any proof in favour of immortality. The rediscovery of theAristotelian corpus favoured the discussion of another anthropological formula. In hisPolitics (I, 2; 1253 a 1-2), Aristotle advanced the idea that man was a “political animal”. This conception opened up the possibility of a political anthropology of whichMarsilius of Padua andDante Alighieri provide remarkable examples. Membership of the human community was perceived as a constitutive element of humanity. In this context, certain authors reflected on communication and discovered thatlanguage was also constitutive of humanity. It is proper to man, said Thomas Aquinas, to use words to express his thoughts: “It is true that the other animals communicate their passions, roughly, as the dog expresses his anger by barking … Hence, man is much more communicative towards others than any animal whatever that we see living gregariously, like the crane, the ant or the bee” (De regno, ch. 1). The theme of the dignity of man manifests yet another aspect of medieval anthropology. An astonishing expression of it appears inJohn Scotus Eriugena’sDe divisione naturae (book IV) where it is said of man that “his substance is the notion by which he knows himself” (PL, 122, 770A). This optimism contrasts with the perspectives sketched out by Lotario dei Segni, the futurePope Innocent III, in the opusculumDe Miseria Condicionis Humane (1195–119) which offers a striking picture of man's weaknesses and infirmities. When in 1452Giannozzo Manetti eulogized the beauty and excellence of man, body and Soul, he wished to reply to the lamentation of Innocent, whose work had an immense success.[39]Giovanni Pico della Mirandola too, in his celebratedDiscourse on the dignity of man, expounded a very high idea of man. Pico celebrated first the radicalfreedom of man, who is capable of choosing himself, i.e. of giving himself his own essence: “I have given you neither a determined place, nor a face of your own, says the creator, nor any particular gift, O Adam, so that your place, your face and your gifts you may will, conquer and possess by yourself. Nature encloses other species in laws established by me. But you, whom no boundary limits, by your own free will, in whose hands I have placed you, define yourself.” This anthropology, which has been celebrated as the beginning of modernity, is not in opposition to religion since this dignity of man belongs to him precisely because he is the image of God according to the biblical word. Yet, with an unprecedented intensity, Pico was able to give a luminous and powerful expression to this profound truth that “man outruns in advance all defined concept of man” (O. Boulnois [fr]).
In Christian theology, there are two ways of "conceiving human nature:" The first is "spiritual, Biblical, and theistic"; and the second is "natural,cosmical, andanti-theistic".[40]: 6 The focus in this section is on the former. AsWilliam James put it in his study of human nature from a religious perspective, "religion" has a "department of human nature".[41]
Various views of human nature have been held by theologians. However, there are some "basic assertions" in all "biblical anthropology:"[42]
TheBible contains no single "doctrine of human nature". Rather, it provides material for more philosophical descriptions of human nature.[43] For example, Creation as found in theBook of Genesis provides a theory on human nature.[44]
Catechism of the Catholic Church, under the chapter "Dignity of the human person", provides an article about man as image of God, vocation tobeatitude, freedom, human acts, passions, moral conscience, virtues, and sin.[45]
As originally created, the Bible describes "two elements" in human nature: "the body and the breath or spirit of life breathed into it by God". By this was created a "living soul", meaning a "living person".[46] According toGenesis 1:27, this living person was made in the "image of God".[47] From the biblical perspective, "to be human is to bear the image of God."[48]: 18
"Two main modes of conceiving human nature—the one of which is spiritual, Biblical, and theistic," and the other "natural, cosmical, and anti-theistic."
Genesis does not elaborate the meaning of "the image of God", but scholars find suggestions. One is that being created in the image of God distinguishes human nature from that of the beasts.[49] Another is that as God is "able to make decisions and rule" so humans made in God's image are "able to make decisions and rule". A third is that humankind possesses an inherent ability "to set goals" and move toward them.[48]: 5, 14 That God denoted creation as "good" suggests that Adam was "created in the image of God, in righteousness".[50]
Adam was created with ability to make "right choices", but also with the ability to choose sin, by which he fell from righteousness into a state of "sin and depravity".[48]: 231 Thus, according to the Bible, "humankind is not as God created it."[51]
ByAdam's fall into sin, "human nature" became "corrupt", although it retains theimage of God. Both theOld Testament and theNew Testament teach that "sin is universal."[48]: 17, 141 For example,Psalm 51:5 reads: "For behold I was conceived in iniquities; and in sins did my mother conceive me."[52] Jesus taught that everyone is a "sinner naturally" because it is humanity's "nature and disposition to sin".[40]: 124–5 Paul, inRomans 7:18, speaks of his "sinful nature".[53]
Such a "recognition that there is something wrong with the moral nature of man is found in all religions."[48]: 141 Augustine of Hippo coined a term for the assessment that all humans are born sinful:original sin.[54] Original sin is "the tendency to sin innate in all human beings".[55] The doctrine of original sin is held by theCatholic Church and most mainstreamProtestant denominations, but rejected by theEastern Orthodox Church, which holds the similar doctrine ofancestral fault.
"The corruption of original sin extends to every aspect of human nature": to "reason and will" as well as to "appetites and impulses". This condition is sometimes called "total depravity".[56] Total depravity does not mean that humanity is as "thoroughly depraved" as it could become.[57] Commenting onRomans 2:14,John Calvin writes that all people have "some notions of justice and rectitude ... which are implanted by nature" all people.[58]
Adam embodied the "whole of human nature" so when Adam sinned "all of human nature sinned."[59] The Old Testament does not explicitly link the "corruption of human nature" to Adam's sin. However, the "universality of sin" implies a link to Adam. In the New Testament, Paul concurs with the "universality of sin". He also makes explicit what the Old Testament implied: the link between humanity's "sinful nature" and Adam's sin[60] InRomans 5:19, Paul writes, "through [Adam's] disobedience humanity became sinful."[61] Paul also applied humanity's sinful nature to himself: "there is nothing good in my sinful nature."[62][63]
The theological "doctrine of original sin" as an inherent element of human nature is not based only on the Bible. It is in part a "generalization from obvious facts" open to empirical observation.[64]
A number of experts on human nature have described the manifestations of original (i.e., the innate tendency to) sin as empirical facts.
Empirical discussion questioning the genetic exclusivity of such an intrinsic badness proposition is presented by researchersElliott Sober andDavid Sloan Wilson. In their book,Unto Others: The Evolution and Psychology of Unselfish Behavior, they propose a theory of multilevelgroup selection in support of an inherent genetic "altruism" in opposition to the original sin exclusivity for human nature.[71]
Liberal theologians in the early 20th century described human nature as "basically good", needing only "proper training and education". But the above examples document the return to a "more realistic view" of human nature "as basically sinful andself-centered". Human nature needs "to be regenerated ... to be able to live the unselfish life".[72]
According tothe Bible, "Adam's disobedience corrupted human nature" but God mercifully "regenerates".[73] "Regeneration is a radical change" that involves a "renewal of our [human] nature".[74] Thus, to counter original sin, Christianity purposes "a complete transformation of individuals" by Christ.[75]
The goal of Christ's coming is that fallen humanity might be "conformed to or transformed into the image of Christ who is the perfect image of God", as in2 Corinthians 4:4.[76] TheNew Testament makes clear the "universal need" for regeneration.[77] A sampling of biblical portrayals of regenerating human nature and the behavioral results follow.
Although this new realism applied to the study of human life from the beginning—for example, inMachiavelli's works—the definitive argument for the final rejection of Aristotle was associated especially withFrancis Bacon. Bacon sometimes wrote as if he accepted the traditional four causes ("It is a correct position that "true knowledge is knowledge by causes." And causes again are not improperly distributed into four kinds: the material, the formal, the efficient, and the final") but he adapted these terms and rejected one of the three:
But of these the final cause rather corrupts than advances the sciences, except such as have to do with human action. The discovery of the formal is despaired of. The efficient and the material (as they are investigated and received, that is, as remote causes, without reference to the latent process leading to the form) are but slight and superficial, and contribute little, if anything, to true and active science.[82]
This line of thinking continued withRené Descartes, whose new approach returned philosophy or science to itspre-Socratic focus upon non-human things.Thomas Hobbes, thenGiambattista Vico, andDavid Hume all claimed to be the first to properly use a modern Baconian scientific approach to human things.
Hobbes famously followed Descartes in describing humanity as matter in motion, just like machines. He also very influentially described man's natural state (without science and artifice) as one where life would be "solitary, poor, nasty, brutish and short".[83] Following him,John Locke's philosophy ofempiricism also saw human nature as atabula rasa. In this view, the mind is at birth a "blank slate" without rules, so data are added, and rules for processing them are formed solely by our sensory experiences.[84]
Jean-Jacques Rousseau pushed the approach of Hobbes to an extreme and criticized it at the same time. He was a contemporary and acquaintance of Hume, writing before theFrench Revolution and long beforeDarwin andFreud. He shockedWestern civilization with hisSecond Discourse by proposing that humans had once been solitary animals, without reason or language or communities, and had developed these things due to accidents of pre-history. (This proposal was also less famously made by Giambattista Vico.) In other words, Rousseau argued that human nature was not only not fixed, but not even approximately fixed compared to what had been assumed before him. Humans are political, and rational, and have language now, but originally they had none of these things.[85] This in turn implied that living under the management of human reason might not be a happy way to live at all, and perhaps there is no ideal way to live. Rousseau is also unusual in the extent to which he took the approach of Hobbes, asserting that primitive humans were not even naturally social. A civilized human is therefore not only imbalanced and unhappy because of the mismatch between civilized life and human nature, but unlike Hobbes, Rousseau also became well known for the suggestion that primitive humans had been happier, "noble savages".[86]
Rousseau's conception of human nature has been seen as the origin of many intellectual and political developments of the 19th and 20th centuries.[87] He was an important influence uponKant,Hegel, andMarx, and the development ofGerman idealism,historicism, andromanticism.
What human nature did entail, according to Rousseau and the other modernists of the 17th and 18th centuries, were animal-like passions that led humanity to develop language and reasoning, and more complex communities (or communities of any kind, according to Rousseau).
In contrast to Rousseau, David Hume was a critic of the oversimplifying and systematic approach of Hobbes, Rousseau, and some others whereby, for example, all human nature is assumed to be driven by variations of selfishness. Influenced byHutcheson andShaftesbury, he argued against oversimplification. On the one hand, he accepted that, for many political and economic subjects, people could be assumed to be driven by such simple selfishness, and he also wrote of some of the more social aspects of "human nature" as something which could be destroyed, for example if people did not associate in just societies. On the other hand, he rejected what he called the "paradox of the sceptics", saying that no politician could have invented words like"'honourable' and 'shameful,' 'lovely' and 'odious,' 'noble' and 'despicable'", unless there was not some natural "original constitution of the mind".[88]
Hume—like Rousseau—was controversial in his own time for his modernist approach, following the example of Bacon and Hobbes, of avoiding consideration of metaphysical explanations for any type of cause and effect. He was accused of being anatheist. He wrote:
We needn't push our researches so far as to ask "Why do we have humanity, i.e. a fellow-feeling with others?" It's enough that we experience this as a force in human nature. Our examination of causes must stop somewhere.[88]
After Rousseau and Hume, the nature of philosophy and science changed, branching into different disciplines and approaches, and the study of human nature changed accordingly. Rousseau's proposal that human nature is malleable became a major influence upon international revolutionary movements of various kinds, while Hume's approach has been more typical in Anglo-Saxon countries, including theUnited States.[89]
According toEdouard Machery, the concept of human nature is an outgrowth offolk biology and in particular, the concept of folk essentialism – the tendency of ordinary people to ascribe essences to kinds. Machery argues that while the idea that humans have an "essence" is a very old idea, the idea that all humans have a unified human nature is relatively modern; for a long time, people thought of humans as "us versus them" and thus did not think of human beings as a unified kind.[90]
The concept of human nature is a source of ongoing debate in contemporary philosophy, specifically withinphilosophy of biology, a subfield of thephilosophy of science. Prominent critics of the concept –David L. Hull,[91]Michael Ghiselin,[92] andDavid Buller;[93] see also[1][2][3] – argue that human nature is incompatible with modernevolutionary biology. Conversely, defenders of the concept argue that when defined in certain ways, human nature is both scientifically respectable and meaningful.[1][2][3][94][95][96] Therefore, the value and usefulness of the concept depends essentially on how one construes it. This section summarizes the prominent construals of human nature and outlines the key arguments from philosophers on both sides of the debate.
Philosopher of scienceDavid L. Hull has influentially argued that there is no such thing as human nature. Hull's criticism is raised against philosophers who conceive human nature as a set of intrinsicphenotypic traits (orcharacters) that are universal among humans, unique to humans, and definitive of what it is to be a member of the biological speciesHomo sapiens. In particular, Hull argues that such "essential sameness of human beings" is "temporary, contingent and relatively rare" in biology.[91] He argues that variation, insofar as it is the result of evolution, is an essential feature of all biological species. Moreover, the type of variation which characterizes a certain species in a certain historical moment is "to a large extent accidental"[91] He writes:[91]: 3
Periodically a biological species might be characterized by one or more characters which are both universally distributed among and limited to the organisms belonging to that species, but such states of affairs are temporary, contingent and relatively rare.
Hull reasons that properties universally shared by all members of a certain species are usually also possessed by members of other species, whereas properties exclusively possessed by the members of a certain species are rarely possessed byall members of that species. For these reasons, Hull observes that, in contemporaryevolutionary taxonomy, belonging to a particular species does not depend on the possession of any specific intrinsic properties. Rather, it depends on standing in the right kind of relations (relations ofgenealogy or interbreeding, depending on the precisespecies concept being used) to other members of the species. Consequently, there can be nointrinsic properties that define what it is to be a member of the speciesHomo sapiens. Individual organisms, including humans, are part of a species by virtue of their relations with other members of the same species, not shared intrinsic properties.
According to Hull, the moral significance of his argument lies in its impact on the biologically legitimate basis for the concept of "human rights". While it has long been argued that there is a sound basis for "human rights" in the idea that all human beings are essentially the same, should Hull's criticism work, such a basis – at least on a biological level – would disappear. Nevertheless, Hull does not perceive this to be a fundamental for human rights, because people can choose to continue respecting human rights even without sharing the same human nature.[91]
Several contemporary philosophers have attempted to defend the notion of human nature against charges that it is incompatible with modern evolutionary biology by proposing alternative interpretations. They claim that the concept of human nature continues to bear relevance in the fields ofneuroscience andevolutionary biology. Many have proposed non-essentialist notions. Others have argued that, even ifnatural selection has shown that any attempt to base species membership on "intrinsic essential properties" is untenable, essences can still be "relational" – this would be consistent with the interbreeding, ecological, andphylogenetic species concepts, which are accepted by modernevolutionary biology.[97] These attempts aim to make natural selection compatible with a certain conception of human nature which is stable across time.
Philosopher of scienceEdouard Machery has proposed that the above criticisms only apply to a specific definition (or "notion") of human nature, and not to "human nature in general".[95] He distinguishes between two different notions:
Machery clarifies that, to count as being "a result of evolution", a property must have anultimate explanation inErnst Mayr's sense. It must be possible to explain the trait as the product of evolutionary processes. Importantly, properties can count as part of human nature in the nomological sense even if they are not universal among humans and not unique to humans. In other words, nomological properties need not be necessary nor sufficient for being human. Instead, it is enough that these properties are shared by most humans, as a result of the evolution of their species – they "need to be typical".[98] Therefore, human nature in the nomological sense does not define what it is to be a member of the speciesHomo sapiens. Examples of properties that count as parts of human nature on the nomological definition include: beingbipedal, having the capacity to speak, having a tendency towardsbiparental investment in children, having fear reactions to unexpected noises.[95] Finally, since they are the product of evolution, properties belonging to the nomological notion of human nature are not fixed, but they can change over time.[98]
Machery agrees with biologists and others philosophers of biology that the essentialist notion of human nature is incompatible with modern evolutionary biology: we cannot explain membership in the human species by means of a definition or a set of properties. However, he maintains that this does not mean humans have no nature, because we can accept the nomological notion which is not a definitional notion. Therefore, we should think of human nature as the many properties humans have in common as a result of evolution.[95]
Machery argues that notions of human nature can help explain why that, while cultures are very diverse, there are also many constants across cultures. For Machery, most forms of cultural diversity are in fact diversity on a common theme; for example, Machery observes that the concept of a kinship system is common across cultures but the exact form it takes and the specifics vary between cultures.[99]
Machery also highlights potential drawbacks of the nomological account.[95] One is that the nomological notion is a watered-down notion that cannot perform many of the roles that the concept of human nature is expected to perform in science and philosophy. The properties endowed upon humans by the nomological account do not distinguish humans from other animals or define what it is to be human. Machery pre-empts this objection by claiming that the nomological concept of human nature still fulfils many roles. He highlights the importance of a conception which picks out what humans share in common which can be used to make scientific, psychological generalizations about human-beings.[98] One advantage of such a conception is that it gives an idea of the traits displayed by the majority of human beings which can be explained in evolutionary terms.
Another potential drawback is that the nomological account of human nature threatens to lead to the absurd conclusion that all properties of humans are parts of human nature. According to the nomological account, a trait is only part of human nature if it is a result of evolution. However, there is a sense in which all human traits are results of evolution. For example, the belief that water is wet is shared by all humans. However, this belief is only possible because we have, for example, evolved a sense of touch. It is difficult to separate traits which are the result of evolution and those which are not. Machery claims the distinction betweenproximate and ultimate explanation can do the work here: only some human traits can be given an ultimate explanation, he argues.
According to the philosopher Richard Samuels[96] the account of human nature is expected to fulfill the five following roles:
Samuels objects that Machery's nomological account fails to deliver on the causal explanatory function, because it claims that superficial and co-varying propertiesare the essence of human nature. Thus, human nature cannot be the underlyingcause of these properties and accordingly cannot fulfill its causal explanatory role.
Philosopher Grant Ramsey also rejects Machery's nomological account. For him, defining human nature with respect to only universal traits fails to capture many important human characteristics.[94] Ramsey quotes the anthropologistClifford Geertz, who claims that "the notion that unless a cultural phenomenon is empirically universal it cannot reflect anything about the nature of man is about as logical as the notion that becausesickle-cell anemia is, fortunately, not universal, it cannot tell us anything about human genetic processes. It is not whether phenomena are empirically common that is critical in science...but whether they can be made to reveal the enduring natural processes that underly them."[100] Following Geertz, Ramsey holds that the study of human nature should not rely exclusively on universal or near-universal traits. There are many idiosyncratic and particular traits of scientific interest. Machery's account of human nature cannot give an account to such differences between men and women as the nomological account only picks out the common features within a species. In this light, the female menstrual cycle which is a biologically an essential and useful feature cannot be included in a nomological account of human nature.[94]
Ramsey[94] also objects that Machery uncritically adopts theinnate-acquired dichotomy, distinguishing between human properties due to enculturation and those due to evolution. Ramsey objects that human properties do not just fall in one of the two categories, writing that "any organismic property is going to be due to both heritable features of the organism as well as the particular environmental features the organism happens to encounter during its life."[94]
Richard Samuels, in an article titled "Science and Human Nature", proposes a causal essentialist view that "human nature should be identified with a suite of mechanisms, processes, and structures that causally explain many of the more superficial properties and regularities reliably associated with humanity."[96] This view is "causal" because the mechanismscausally explain the superficial properties reliably associated with humanity by referencing the underlying causal structures the properties belong to. For example, it is true that the belief that water is wet is shared by all humans yet it is not in itself a significant aspect of human nature. Instead, the psychological process that lead us to assign the word "wetness" to water is a universal trait shared by all human beings. In this respect, the superficial belief that water is wet reveals an important causal psychological process which is widely shared by most human beings. The explanation is also "essentialist" because there is a core set of empirically discoverable cognitive mechanism that count as part of the human nature. According to Samuels, his view avoids the standard biological objections to human nature essentialism.
Samuels argues that the theoretical roles of human nature includes: organizing role, descriptive functions, causal explanatory functions, taxonomic functions, and invariances.
In comparison with traditional essentialist view, the "causal essentialist" view does not accomplish the taxonomic role of human nature (the role of defining what it is to be human). He claims however, that no conception could achieve this, as the fulfillment of the role would not survive evolutionary biologists’ objections (articulated above by in "Criticisms of the concept of human nature"). In comparison with Machery's nomological conception, Samuels wants to restore the causal-explanatory function of human nature. He defines the essence of human nature as causal mechanisms and not as surface-level properties. For instance, on this view, linguistic behaviour is not part of human nature, but the cognitive mechanisms underpinning linguistic behaviour might count as part of human nature.
Grant Ramsey proposes an alternative account of human nature, which he names the "life-history trait cluster" account.[94] This view stems from the recognition that the combination of a specific genetic constitution with a specific environment is not sufficient to determine how a life will go, i.e., whether one is rich, poor, dies old, dies young, etc. Many ‘life histories’ are possible for a given individual, each populated by a great number of traits. Ramsey defines his conception of human nature in reference to the “pattern of trait clusters within the totality of extant possible life-histories”.[94] In other words, there are certain life histories, i.e., possible routes one's life can take, for example: being rich, being a PhD student, or getting ill. Ramsey underlines the patterns behind these possible routes by delving into the causes of these life histories. For example, one can make the following claim: “Humans sweat when they get exhausted" or one can also propose neurological claims such as “Humans secrete Adrenaline when they are in flight-fight mode.” This approach enables Ramsey to go beyond the superficial appearances and understand the similarities/differences between individuals in a deeper level which refers to the causal mechanisms (processes, structures and constraints etc.) which lie beneath them. Once we list all the possible life-histories of an individual, we can find these causal patterns and add them together to form the basis of individual nature.
Ramsey's next argumentative manoeuvre is to point out that traits are not randomly scattered across potential life histories; there are patterns. “These patterns” he states “provide the basis for the notion of individual and human nature”.[94]: 987 While one's ‘individual nature’ consists of the pattern of trait clusters distributed across that individual's set of possible life histories, Human Nature, Ramsey defines as “the pattern of trait clusters within the totality of extant human possible life histories”.[94]: 987 Thus, if we were to combine all possible life histories of all individuals in existence we would have access to the trait distribution patterns that constitute human nature.
Trait patterns, on Ramsey's account, can be captured in the form ofconditional statements, such as "if female, you developovaries" or "if male, you developtestes." These statements will not be true of all humans. Ramsey contends that these statements capture part of human nature if they have a good balance ofpervasiveness (many people satisfy theantecedent of the conditional statement), androbustness (many people who satisfy the antecedent go on to satisfy theconsequent).
Hereditarianism is the research program according to whichheredity plays a central role in determining human nature and character traits, such asintelligence andpersonality. Hereditarians believe in the power ofgenetic influences toexplain human behavior and solve human social-political problems. They stress the value ofevolutionary explanations in all areas of thehuman sciences.
Most prominently inintelligence research, they purport thatgenetic predisposition determinesindividual life outcomes more than do either structuredenvironmental influences (i.e.nurture) ordevelopmental noise respectively.Instinctual behaviour, an inherent inclination towards a particular complex behaviour, has been observed in humans.Emotions such asfear are part of human nature (seeFear § Innate fear for example). However they are also known to have been malleable and not fixed (seeneuroplasticity andFear § Inability to experience fear).
Congenitalfear of snakes and spiders was found in six-month-old babies.[101]Infant cry is a manifestation of instinct. The infant cannot otherwise protect itself for survival during its long period of maturation. Thematernal instinct, manifest particularly in response to the infant cry, has long been respected as one of the most powerful. Its mechanism has been partly elucidated by observations with functional MRI of the mother's brain.[102]
Theherd instinct is found in human children andchimpanzee cubs, but is apparently absent in youngorangutans.[103]
Squeamishness anddisgust in humans is an instinct developed during evolution to protect the body and avoid infection by various diseases.[104]
The socioeconomic environment of humans are a context which affect theirbrain development.[105] It has been argued thatH. sapiens is unsustainable by nature – thatunsustainability is an inevitable emergent property of his unaltered nature.[106] It has also been argued that human nature is not necessarily resulting in unsustainability but is embedded in and affected by a socioeconomic system that is not having an inevitable structure[107][additional citation(s) needed] – that the contemporary socioeconomic macrosystem affects human activities.[108] A paper published in 1997 concluded that humanity suffer consequences of a "poor fit" between inherited natures and "many of the constructed environments in organizational society".[109] Designing a "cultural narrative" explicitly for living on a finite planet may be suitable for overriding "outdated" innate tendencies.[106]
Human nature – which some have argued to vary to some extent per individual and in time, not be static and, at least in the future, to some extent be purposely alterable[110] – is one of the factors that shape which, how and when human activities are conducted. The contemporary socioeconomic and collective decision-making mechanisms are structures that may affect the expression of human nature – for instance, innate tendencies to seek survival, well-being, respect and status that some consider fundamental to humans[111] may result in varying product-designs, types of work,public infrastructure-designs and the distribution and prevalence of each. As with thenature versus nurture debate, which is concerned whether – or to which degrees – human behavior is determined by the environment or by a person's genes, scientific research is inconclusive about the degree to which human nature is shaped by and manageable bysystemic structures as well as about how and to which degrees these structures can and should be purposely altered swiftly globally.
{{cite book}}
:|journal=
ignored (help){{cite book}}
: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link){{cite book}}
:|journal=
ignored (help)